Well-founded relation

from Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In mathematics is one of a quantity defined binary relation is well-founded if there is no infinite chains are in this relation, d. H. when there is no infinite sequence of elements in with for all . In particular, a well-founded relation does not contain any cycles.

properties

Well-founded relations are always irreflexive .

Using the theorem of the excluded third party and the axiom of dependent choice , the following statements about are equivalent:

  • is well founded.
  • The transitive envelope of is well founded.
  • Every non-empty subset has a minimal element; H. one for which there is no with .
  • Well-founded induction over is a valid principle to prove statements about all elements of .

Examples

  • The predecessor relation to , defined by , is well founded. The induction principle that goes with it is that of complete induction . Its transitive envelope is the usual -relation with the associated induction principle of strong (complete) induction ; with classical logic equivalent to infinite descent .
  • All well-founded orders and all well -founded relationships are well-founded relations if one only looks at the non-reflective part. The inversions do not apply, since well-founded relations do not have to be transitive.
  • A model of the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory defines a relation that is well-founded due to the axiom of foundation . The associated induction principle is called epsilon induction .

Relationships between the definitions

With the following definitions are possible for that it is well founded:

  1. is classically well-founded ( inhabited subsets have a minimal element) .
  2. is well-founded (well-founded induction is valid) .
  3. Regarding there is no infinite descent (formulated relational) : .
  4. Regarding there is no infinite descent : .

Obviously, (1) and (3) are equivalent to each other when using classical logic.

Constructively can each member of the Implikationskette prove but the other direction generally not.

requires an instance of the axiom of dependent choice .

For classical logic is needed, in a very strong sense: The existence of a classically well-founded relation and elements with already follows the law of the excluded . In this sense, the classical well-foundedness (1) is too strong for constructive mathematics. Since there are usually inhabited relations well-founded according to (2), classical logic implies .

See also

literature

  • Paul Taylor: Practical Foundations of Mathematics , Cambridge University Press, 1999, ISBN 0-521-63107-6 , pp. 97ff