Quasitransitive relation

from Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
The quasitransitive relation . Its symmetrical part is shown in blue, its transitive part in green.

Quasi-transitivity is a watered- down version of transitivity used in social choice theory and microeconomics . Informally speaking, a relation is quasi-transitory if it is symmetric for some values ​​and transitive for others. The concept was introduced in 1969 by Amartya K. Sen to investigate the consequences of the Arrow theorem .

Examples

Some authors regard economic preferences as quasitransitive (and not as transitive). The classic example is a person who is undecided between 7 and 8 grams of sugar and also undecided between 8 and 9 grams of sugar, but who prefers 9 grams of sugar over 7. Similarly, the Sorites paradox can be resolved by weakening the assumed transitivity of certain relations to quasitransitivity.

Formal definition

A two-digit relation over a set is quasitransitive if the following applies to all :

.

If the relation is also antisymmetric, T is transitive.

An alternate definition uses the asymmetrical, or “strict” part of , defined by ; thus is quasitransitive if and only if is transitive.

properties

  • A relation is quasi-transitive if and only if it is the disjoint union of a symmetric relation and a transitive relation . and are not clearly determined by; however, that is minimal from the " " evidence.
  • As a result, every symmetric relation is quasi-transitive, just like every transitive relation. In addition, an antisymmetric and quasi-transitive relation is always also transitive.
  • The relation {(7.7), (7.8), (7.9), (8.7), (8.8), (8.9), (9.8), (9.9) } from the sugar example above is quasi-transitive, but not transitive.
  • A quasitransitive relation does not have to correspond to an acyclic graph : for every non-empty set the universal relation is the Cartesian product both cyclic and quasitransitive.

credentials

  1. Amartya K. Sen: Quasi-Transitivity, Rational Choice and Collective Decisions . In: The Review of Economic Studies . tape 36 , 1969, p. 381-393 .
  2. Robert Duncan Luce: Semi Orders and a Theory of Utility Discrimination . In: Econometrica . tape 24 , no. 2 , April 1956, p. 178–191 ( online [PDF]). Here: p. 179; Luce's original example consists of 400 comparisons (of coffee cups with different amounts of sugar) instead of just 2.
  3. The naming follows (Bossert, Suzumura 2009), pp. 2–3. - " ": Define and , then is symmetrical by construction and the transitivity of is identical to the definition of the quasitransitivity of . - " ": Let be the disjoint union of symmetrical and transitive and hold , then follows and , since or would contradict the assumptions or . Hence it follows because of transitivity, because of disjointness, because of symmetry. would therefore imply and, because of transitivity, also what contradicts. Overall this proves .
  4. If R z. B. is an equivalence relation , J can be chosen as the empty relation or as R itself and P each as complement R \ J.
  5. If xRy ∧ ¬ yRx holds for a given R , the pair ( x , y ) cannot belong to the symmetric part, it must therefore belong to the transitive part in any case.
  6. Since the empty relation is trivially both transitive and symmetric.
  7. The antisymmetry of R makes the coreflexivity ( s ) of J necessary, so the union of J and the transitive part P is again transitive.
  • Frederic Schick: Arrow's Proof and the Logic of Preference . In: Philosophy of Science . tape 36 , no. 2 , June 1969, p. 127-144 , JSTOR : 186166 (English).
  • Walter Bossert, Kotaro Suzumura: Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations . March 2009 (English, technical report [PDF] Université de Montréal, Waseda University Tokyo).