Empress Matilda and Time travel: Difference between pages

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Difference between pages)
Content deleted Content added
m Undid revision 244404102 by 66.92.255.146 (talk)
 
m Reverted edits by 74.187.62.202 (talk) to last version by Graham87
 
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Refimprove|date=January 2008}}
{{Infobox British Royalty|majesty
{{Cleanup|date=November 2007}}
| name = Matilda
:''This article details time travel itself. For other uses, see [[Time Traveler]].''
| title = Lady of the English; Countess of Anjou<br> Holy Roman Empress; German Queen
{{unsolved|physics|Is '''time travel''' theoretically and practically possible? If so, how can [[paradox]]es such as the [[grandfather paradox]] be avoided?}}
| image = Empress matilda.jpg
'''Time travel''' is the concept of moving between different moments in [[time]] in a manner analogous to moving between different points in [[space]], either sending objects (or in some cases just information) backwards in time to a moment before the present, or sending objects forward from the present to the future without the need to experience the intervening period (at least not at the normal rate). Some interpretations of time travel also suggest that an attempt to travel backwards in time might take one to a [[Multiverse|parallel universe]] whose history would begin to diverge from the traveler's original history after the moment the traveler arrived in the past.<ref name="deutsch">{{cite journal|last=Deutsch| first=David| authorlink = David Deutsch|date=1991| title=Quantum mechanics near closed timelike curves| journal=Physical Review D| volume=44| pages=3197–3217| doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.44.3197}}</ref> Although time travel has been a common [[plot device]] in [[fiction]] since the 19th century, and one-way travel into the future is arguably possible given the phenomenon of [[time dilation]] based on velocity in the theory of [[special relativity]] (exemplified by the [[twin paradox]]) as well as [[gravitational time dilation]] in the theory of [[general relativity]], it is currently unknown whether the [[laws of physics]] would allow backwards time travel. Any technological device, whether fictional or hypothetical, that is used to achieve two-way time travel is known as a '''[[time machine]]'''.
| imgw = 200
| reign = April – November 1141<br />[[7 January]] [[1114]] – [[23 May]] [[1125]]
| reign-type = Reign'''<br />''Empress consort''
| predecessor = [[Stephen of England|Stephen]]
| successor = [[Stephen of England|Stephen]]
| spouse = [[Henry V, Holy Roman Emperor]]<br />m. 1114 dec. 1125<br />[[Geoffrey V, Count of Anjou]]<br />m. 1128 dec. 1151
| spouse-type = Consort to<br /><br />Consort
| issue = [[Henry II of England|Henry II]]<br>[[Geoffrey VI, Count of Anjou]]<br>[[William, Count of Poitou]]
| titles = Lady of the English<br />Countess of Anjou<br />[[List of Holy Roman Empresses and German queens#Salian Dynasty|Holy Roman Empress]]
| royal house = [[House of Plantagenet]]<br />[[Salian dynasty]]<br />[[House of Normandy]]
| father = [[Henry I of England|Henry I]]
| mother = [[Matilda of Scotland]]
| date of birth = [[7 February]] [[1102]]
| place of birth = [[Winchester]]
| date of death = [[10 September]] [[1167]]
| place of death = [[Rouen]]
| place of burial = [[Rouen]]
}}
'''Empress Matilda''' (sometimes '''Maud''' or '''Maude'''; later '''Countess of Anjou''' and '''Lady of the English'''; [[7 February]] [[1102]] &ndash; [[10 September]] [[1167]]) was the daughter and dispossessed [[heir]] of [[Henry I of England]]. She was married to [[Henry V, Holy Roman Emperor]], and then to [[Geoffrey V, Count of Anjou]], by whom she became the mother of [[Henry II of England]].


==Origins of the concept==
Matilda was the first female ruler, although uncrowned and for a brief time, of the [[Kingdom of England]]. Her failure to secure that rule meant that her temporary and disputed period of reign in 1141 was extremely brief. She is often excluded from lists of English monarchs and even the official British monarchy website excludes her, listing [[Stephen of England]] as king from 1135-1154.
There is no widespread agreement as to which written work should be recognized as the earliest example of a time travel story, since a number of early works feature elements ambiguously suggestive of time travel. For example, ''Memoirs of the Twentieth Century'' (1733) by [[Samuel Madden]] is mainly a series of letters from English ambassadors in various countries to the British "Lord High Treasurer", along with a few replies from the British Foreign Office, all purportedly written in 1997 and 1998 and describing the conditions of that era.<ref name="madden1">{{cite book | last = Alkon | first = Paul K. | title = Origins of Futuristic Fiction | publisher = The University of Georgia Press | date= 1987 | pages = 95-96 | isbn = 0-8203-0932-X }}</ref> However, the framing story is that these letters were actual documents given to the narrator by his [[guardian angel]] one night in 1728; for this reason, Paul Alkon suggests in his book ''Origins of Futuristic Fiction'' that "the first time-traveler in English literature is a guardian angel who returns with state documents from 1998 to the year 1728",<ref name="madden2">{{cite book | last = Alkon | first = Paul K. | title = Origins of Futuristic Fiction | publisher = The University of Georgia Press | date= 1987 | pages = 85 | isbn = 0-8203-0932-X }}</ref> although the book does not explicitly show how the angel obtained these documents. Alkon later qualifies this by writing "It would be stretching our generosity to praise Madden for being the first to show a traveler arriving ''from'' the future", but also says that Madden "deserves recognition as the first to toy with the rich idea of time-travel in the form of an artifact sent backwards from the future to be discovered in the present."<ref name="madden1" />


[[Louis-Sébastien Mercier]]'s ''L'An 2440, rêve s'il en fût jamais'' ("The Year 2440: A Dream If Ever There Were One") is a utopian novel set in the year 2440. An extremely popular work (it went through twenty-five editions after its first appearance in 1771), the work describes the adventures of an unnamed man, who, after engaging in a heated discussion with a philosopher friend about the injustices of Paris, falls asleep and finds himself in a Paris of the future. Robert Darnton writes that "despite its self-proclaimed character of fantasy...L'An 2440 demanded to be read as a serious guidebook to the future." [Robert ''Darnton, The Forbidden Best-Sellers of Pre-Revolutionary France'' (New York: W.W. Norton, 1996), 120.]
As many of her contemporaries or near contemporaries were also called ''Matilda'' in Latin texts, she is sometimes called ''Maude'' to distinguish her. This is merely a modernised spelling of the Norman-French form of her name, Mahaut.


In the science fiction anthology ''Far Boundaries'' (1951), the editor [[August Derleth]] identifies the short story ''"Missing One's Coach: An Anachronism"'', written for the ''[http://books.google.com/books?id=jfPAwAnj9JUC Dublin Literary Magazine]'' by an [[Anonymity|anonymous]] author in 1838, as a very early time travel story.<ref name="derleth">{{cite book | last = Derleth | first = August | authorlink = August Derleth | title = Far Boundaries | publisher = Pellegrini & Cudahy | date= 1951 | pages = 3}}</ref> In this story, the narrator is waiting under a tree to be picked up by a [[Stagecoach|coach]] which will take him out of [[Newcastle upon Tyne|Newcastle]], when he suddenly finds himself transported back over a thousand years, where he encounters the [[Bede|Venerable Bede]] in a [[monastery]], and gives him somewhat ironic explanations of the developments of the coming centuries. It is never entirely clear whether these events actually occurred or were merely a dream — the narrator says that when he initially found a comfortable-looking spot in the roots of the tree, he sat down, "and as my sceptical reader will tell me, nodded and slept", but then says that he is "resolved not to admit" this explanation. A number of dreamlike elements of the story may suggest otherwise to the reader, such as the fact that none of the members of the monastery seem to be able to see him at first, and the abrupt ending where Bede has been delayed talking to the narrator and so the other monks burst in thinking that some harm has come to him, and suddenly the narrator finds himself back under the tree in the present (August of 1837), with his coach having just passed his spot on the road, leaving him stranded in Newcastle for another night.<ref name="missingcoach">{{cite book | last = Derleth | first = August | authorlink = August Derleth | title = Far Boundaries | publisher = Pellegrini & Cudahy | date= 1951 | pages = 11-38}}</ref>
== Holy Roman Empress ==
Matilda was born on 7 February 1102<ref>Brian Tompsett "Royal Genealogy Directory"</ref> to [[Henry I of England]] and his wife [[Matilda of Scotland]]. Her maternal grandparents were [[Malcolm III of Scotland]] and [[Saint Margaret of Scotland]].
Margaret was a daughter of [[Edward the Exile]] and granddaughter of [[Edmund II of England]].


[[Charles Dickens]]' 1843 book ''[[A Christmas Carol]]'' is considered by some<ref name="Scrooge">{{cite web |url=http://www.towson.edu/~flynn/timetv.html |title=Time Travel Literature |accessdate=2006-10-28 |author=Flynn, John L.}}</ref> to be one of the first depictions of time travel, as the main character, Ebenezer Scrooge, is transported to Christmases past, present and yet to come. These might be considered mere visions rather than actual time travel, though, since Scrooge only viewed each time period passively, unable to interact with them.
Her birth is generally said to have taken place at [[Winchester]], though recent research by the late John Fletcher (1990) suggests it may have occurred at the royal palace at [[Sutton Courtenay]] in [[Oxfordshire]].


A clearer example of time travel is found in the popular 1861 book ''Paris avant les hommes (Paris before Men)'' by the French botanist and geologist [[Pierre Boitard]], published posthumously. In this story the main character is transported into the prehistoric past by the magic of a "lame demon" (a French pun on Boitard's name), where he encounters such extinct animals as a [[Plesiosaur]], as well as Boitard's imagined version of an apelike human ancestor, and is able to actively interact with some of them.<ref name="boitard">{{cite book | last = Rudwick | first = Martin J. S. | title = Scenes From Deep Time | publisher = The University of Chicago Press | date= 1992 | pages = 166-169 | isbn = 0-226-73105-7 }}</ref> Another clear early example of time travel in fiction is the short story ''{{PDFlink|[http://www.horrormasters.com/Text/a2221.pdf The Clock That Went Backward]|35.7&nbsp;KB}}'' by [[Edward Page Mitchell]], which appeared in the ''[[New York Sun (historical)|New York Sun]]'' in 1881. [[Mark Twain]]'s ''[[A Connecticut Yankee in King Arthur's Court]]'' (1889), in which the protagonist finds himself in the time of [[King Arthur]] after a fight in which he is hit with a sledge hammer, was another early time travel story which helped bring the concept to a wide audience, and was also one of the first stories to show history being changed by the time traveler's actions.
When she was seven years old, Matilda was [[betrothed]] to [[Henry V, Holy Roman Emperor]], and was sent to the [[Holy Roman Empire]] in 1111 to begin her training as his [[consort]]. Matilda and Henry were married at [[Worms, Germany|Worms]] on [[January 7]], [[1114]] in a splendid ceremony. In March 1116 Matilda and Henry visited [[Rome]] and [[Tuscany]], and she acted as [[Regent]] in his absence.


The first time travel story to feature time travel by means of a time ''machine'' was [[Enrique Gaspar y Rimbau]]'s 1887 book ''El Anacronópete''.<ref name="firsttimemachine">{{cite journal | last = Uribe | first = Augusto | title = The First Time Machine: Enrique Gaspar's Anacronópete | journal = [[The New York Review of Science Fiction]] | volume = Vol. 11, No. 10 | issue = 130 | pages = 12 |date=June 1999}}</ref> This idea gained popularity with the [[H. G. Wells]] story ''[[The Time Machine]]'', published in 1895 (preceded by a less influential story of time travel Wells wrote in 1888, titled ''[[The Chronic Argonauts]]''), which also featured a time machine and which is often seen as an inspiration for all later science fiction stories featuring time travel.
When Henry died in 1125, he left Matilda a childless widow of twenty-three. The Imperial couple allegedly had no surviving offspring. Hermann of Tournai states that Maud bore a child that lived only a short while. Matilda's brother, [[William Adelin]], had perished several years before in the wreck of the [[White Ship]], leaving Matilda the only legitimate heir to the [[Kingdom of England|English throne]].


Since that time, both science and fiction (see [[Time travel in fiction]]) have expanded on the concept of time travel, but whether it could be possible in reality is still an open question.
Despite being known most popularly by the title of "[[Empress]]" due to her first marriage, Matilda's right to the title was dubious. She was never crowned Holy Roman Empress by a legitimate [[Pope]] (generally recognised as required to claim the title), only as [[German Queen]] by her husband's Bishops and formally her correct title was "Queen of the Romans". However, "Empress" was arguably an appropriate courtesy title for the wife of an Emperor who had been crowned by the Pope, and indeed, in later years she encouraged chroniclers to believe that the Pope had crowned her.


==Time travel in theory==
== Second marriage to Geoffrey of Anjou ==
Some theories, most notably [[special relativity|special]] and [[general relativity]], suggest that suitable geometries of [[spacetime]], or specific types of motion in [[space]], might allow time travel into the past and future if these geometries or motions are possible.<ref name="Thorne1">{{cite book | last = Thorne | first = Kip S. | authorlink = Kip Thorne | title = [[Black Holes and Time Warps]] | publisher = W. W. Norton | date= 1994 | pages = p. 499 | id = ISBN 0-393-31276-3}}</ref> In technical papers physicists generally avoid the commonplace language of "moving" or "traveling" through time ('movement' normally refers only to a change in spatial position as the time coordinate is varied), and instead discuss the possibility of [[closed timelike curve]]s, which are [[worldline]]s that form closed loops in spacetime, allowing objects to return to their own past. There are known to be solutions to the equations of general relativity that describe spacetimes which contain closed timelike curves{{Fact|date=August 2008}}, but the physical plausibility of these solutions is uncertain.


Physicists take for granted that if one were to move away from the Earth at [[special relativity|relativistic]] velocities and return, more time would have passed on Earth than for the traveler, so in this sense it is accepted that relativity allows "travel into the future" (although according to relativity there is no single objective answer to how much time has 'really' passed between the departure and the return). On the other hand, many in the scientific community believe that backwards time travel is highly unlikely. Any theory which would allow time travel would require that issues of [[causality (physics)|causality]] be resolved. The classic example of a problem involving causality is the "[[grandfather paradox]]": what if one were to go back in time and kill one's own grandfather before one's father was conceived? But some scientists believe that paradoxes can be avoided, either by appealing to the [[Novikov self-consistency principle]] or to the notion of branching [[multiverse|parallel universes]] (see [[Time travel#The possibility of paradoxes|the possibility of paradoxes]] below).
Matilda returned to [[Kingdom of England|England]], where her father named her his heir with the agreement of the Anglo-Norman barons, who swore (in 1127) to accept her as ruler if Henry I had no son, and arranged another marriage for her. On [[June 17]], [[1128]], she was married again, at [[Le Mans]] in [[Anjou]], to [[Geoffrey V, Count of Anjou|Geoffrey of Anjou]], who was eleven years her junior. He was nicknamed "[[Plantagenet]]" from the [[broom (shrub)|broom]] flower (''planta genista'') which he took as his emblem, hence the name of the line of English kings descended from him. He was at this time [[Count of Maine]] and heir to his father [[Fulk of Jerusalem|Fulk V of Anjou]].


===Tourism in time===
The marriage was not a happy one, and Matilda separated from him and returned to her father. She returned to Geoffrey in 1131, and they were reconciled. They produced three sons, the eldest of whom, [[Henry II of England|Henry]], was born on [[March 5]], [[1133]]. The birth of her second son, [[Geoffrey, Count of Nantes]], in 1134, was difficult and Matilda nearly died in childbirth. Her third son, born in 1136, was [[William, Count of Poitou]]. Her father [[Henry I of England|King Henry]] came to visit and took "great delight" in his grandsons.{{Fact|date=March 2008}} King Henry and Geoffrey quarreled, and so when her father died on [[December 1]], [[1135]] in [[Normandy]], Matilda was with Geoffrey in [[Anjou]].
[[Stephen Hawking]] once suggested that the absence of [[tourist]]s from the future constitutes an argument against the existence of time travel&mdash;a variant of the [[Fermi paradox]]. Of course this would not prove that time travel is physically impossible, since it might be that time travel is physically possible but that it is never in fact developed (or is cautiously never used); and even if it is developed, Hawking notes elsewhere that time travel might only be possible in a region of spacetime that is warped in the right way, and that if we cannot create such a region until the future, then time travelers would not be able to travel back before that date, so "This picture would explain why we haven't been over run by tourists from the future."<ref name="Hawking warp">{{cite web |url=http://www.hawking.org.uk/lectures/warps3.html |title=Space and Time Warps |accessdate=2006-11-20 |author=Hawking, Steven |format=html}}</ref> [[Carl Sagan]] also once suggested the possibility that time travelers could be here, but are disguising their existence or are not recognized as time travelers.<ref>[http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/time/sagan.html NOVA Online - Sagan on Time Travel]</ref>


===General relativity===
== Struggle for throne of England ==
However, the theory of [[general relativity]] does suggest scientific grounds for thinking backwards time travel could be possible in certain unusual scenarios, although arguments from [[semiclassical gravity]] suggest that when [[quantum mechanics|quantum]] effects are incorporated into general relativity, these loopholes may be closed.<ref>http://arxiv.org/pdf/gr-qc/0204022</ref> These semiclassical arguments led Hawking to formulate the [[chronology protection conjecture]], suggesting that the fundamental laws of nature prevent time travel,<ref name="chronology protection1">{{cite journal | first=Stephen | last=Hawking | authorlink = Stephen Hawking | url=http://link.aps.org/abstract/PRD/v46/p603 | title=Chronology protection conjecture | journal = Physical Review D | volume = 46 | year=1992 | doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.46.603 | pages=603}}</ref> but physicists cannot come to a definite judgment on the issue without a theory of [[quantum gravity]] to join quantum mechanics and general relativity into a completely unified theory.<ref name="futureofspacetime1">{{cite book | last = Hawking | first = Stephen | authorlink = Stephen Hawking | coauthors = [[Kip Thorne]], [[Igor Dmitriyevich Novikov|Igor Novikov]], [[Timothy Ferris]], [[Alan Lightman]] | title = The Future of Spacetime | publisher = W. W. Norton |date= 2002 | pages = p. 150 | id = ISBN 0-393-02022-3}}</ref>


==Time travel to the past in physics==
{{House of Plantagenet|matilda|Blason duche fr Normandie.svg|right}}
Time travel to the past is theoretically allowed using the following methods:<ref name="Gott">{{cite journal | first = J. Richard | last = Gott | title = Time Travel in Einstein's Universe | year = 2002}} p.33-130 </ref>
On the death of her father, Henry I, in 1135, Matilda expected to succeed to the throne of [[Kingdom of England|England]], but her cousin, [[Stephen of England|Stephen of Blois]], a nephew of Henry I, usurped the throne with the support of most of the barons, breaking the oath he had previously made to defend her rights. An immediate reason for this was that Stephen was in England, whilst Matilda was in Anjou. The [[The Anarchy|civil war which followed]] was bitter and prolonged, with neither side gaining the ascendancy for long, but it was not until 1139 that Matilda could command the military strength necessary to challenge Stephen within his own realm. Stephen's wife, the Countess of Boulogne who was also named [[Matilda of Boulogne|Matilda]], was the Empress's maternal cousin. During the war, Matilda's most loyal and capable supporter was her illegitimate half-brother, [[Robert, 1st Earl of Gloucester|Robert of Gloucester]].
*Space traveling [[Faster-than-light|faster than the speed of light]]
*The use of [[cosmic string]]s and [[black holes]]
*[[Wormhole]]s and [[Alcubierre drive|Alcubierre 'warp' drive]]


===The equivalence of time travel and faster-than-light travel===
Matilda's greatest triumph came in April 1141, when her forces defeated and captured King Stephen at the [[Battle of Lincoln (1141)]]. He was made a prisoner and effectively deposed. Although she now controlled the kingdom, Matilda never styled herself Queen but took the title "Lady of the English", possibly modeled on the Anglo-Saxon practice of naming female rulers "Lady of the..." such as King Alfred the Great's daughter [[Ethelfleda]], Lady of the Mercians. Also the term Queen in Anglo-Saxon (cwen) had the connotation of wife, not a female ruler, so the distinction was necessary.
If one were able to move information or matter from one point to another [[faster than light]], then according to [[special relativity]], there would be some [[inertial frame of reference]] in which the signal or object was moving backwards in time. This is a consequence of the [[relativity of simultaneity]] in special relativity, which says that in some cases different reference frames will disagree on whether two events at different locations happened "at the same time" or not, and they can also disagree on the order of the two events (technically, these disagreements occur when [[Spacetime#Space-time intervals|spacetime interval]] between the events is 'space-like', meaning that neither event lies in the future [[light cone]] of the other).<ref name="Jarrell">{{cite web |url=http://www.physics.uc.edu/~jarrell/COURSES/ELECTRODYNAMICS/Chap11/chap11.pdf |title=The Special Theory of Relativity |accessdate=2006-10-27 |author=Jarrell, Mark |format=PDF |pages=7-11}}</ref> If one of the two events represents the sending of a signal from one location and the second event represents the reception of the same signal at another location, then as long as the signal is moving at the speed of light or slower, the mathematics of simultaneity ensures that all reference frames agree that the transmission-event happened before the reception-event.<ref name="Jarrell" /> However, in the case of a hypothetical signal moving faster than light, there would always be some frames in which the signal was received before it was sent, so that the signal could be said to have moved backwards in time. And since one of the two fundamental [[postulates of special relativity]] says that the laws of physics should work the same way in every inertial frame, then if it is possible for signals to move backwards in time in any one frame, it must be possible in all frames. This means that if observer A sends a signal to observer B which moves FTL (faster than light) in A's frame but backwards in time in B's frame, and then B sends a reply which moves FTL in B's frame but backwards in time in A's frame, it could work out that A receives the reply before sending the original signal, a clear violation of [[Causality (physics)|causality]] in ''every'' frame. An illustration of such a scenario using [[Minkowski diagram|spacetime diagrams]] can be found [http://www.theculture.org/rich/sharpblue/archives/000089.html here].


According to [[special relativity]] it would take an infinite amount of energy to accelerate a slower-than-light object to the speed of light, and although relativity does not forbid the theoretical possibility of [[tachyons]] which move faster than light at all times, when analyzed using [[quantum field theory]] it seems that it would not actually be possible to use them to transmit information faster than light,<ref name="tachyon">{{cite web |url=http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/physics/ParticleAndNuclear/tachyons.html |title=Tachyons entry from Usenet Physics FAQ |accessdate=2006-10-27 |author=Chase, Scott I.}}</ref> and there is no evidence for their existence.
Her advantage lasted only a few months. When she marched on [[London]], the city was ready to welcome her and support a coronation. However, she refused the citizens' request to have their taxes halved. On 24 June 1141, she found the gates of London shut and the civil war reignited. By November, Stephen was free, having been exchanged for the captured [[Robert of Gloucester]], Matilda's half-brother, and a year later, the tables were turned when Matilda was besieged at [[Oxford]] but escaped to [[Wallingford]], supposedly by fleeing across the snow-covered land in a white cape. In 1141 she had escaped [[Devizes]] in a similarly clever manner, by disguising herself as a corpse and being carried out for burial. In 1148, Matilda was finally forced to return to [[France]], following the death of [[Robert, 1st Earl of Gloucester|Robert of Gloucester]].


===Special spacetime geometries===
==Later life==
The [[general theory of relativity]] extends the [[Special relativity|special theory]] to cover gravity, illustrating it in terms of curvature in spacetime caused by mass-energy and the flow of momentum. General relativity describes the universe under a system of [[Einstein field equations|field equations]], and there exist solutions to these equations that permit what are called "[[closed time-like curve]]s," and hence time travel into the past.<ref name="Thorne1">{{cite journal | first = Thorne| last = Kip S. | title = [[Black Holes and Time Warps]] | year = }} p. 499 </ref>The first of these was proposed by [[Kurt Gödel]], a solution known as the [[Gödel metric]], but his (and many others') example requires the universe to have physical characteristics that it does not appear to have.<ref name="Thorne1">{{cite journal | first = Thorne| last = Kip S. | title = [[Black Holes and Time Warps]] | year = }} p. 499</ref> Whether general relativity forbids closed time-like curves for all realistic conditions is unknown .
Not all hope was lost. Matilda's son, ([[Henry II of England|Henry]]), was showing signs of becoming a successful leader. Although the civil war had been decided in Stephen's favour, his reign was troubled. In 1153, the death of his son Eustace, combined with the arrival of a military expedition led by Henry, led him to acknowledge the latter as his heir by the [[Treaty of Wallingford]].


===Using wormholes===
Matilda retired to [[Rouen]] in [[Normandy]] during her last years, where she maintained her own court and presided over the government of the [[duchy]] in the absence of Henry. She intervened in the quarrels between her eldest son Henry and her second son Geoffrey, but peace between the brothers was brief. Geoffrey rebelled against Henry twice before his sudden death in 1158. Relations between Henry and his youngest brother, [[William, Count of Poitou|William]], were more cordial, and William was given vast estates in England. [[Archbishop]] [[Thomas Becket]] refused to allow William to marry the Countess of Surrey and the young man fled to Matilda's court at Rouen. William, who was his mother's favourite child, died there in January 1164, reportedly of disappointment and sorrow. She attempted to mediate in the quarrel between her son Henry and Becket, but was unsuccessful.
[[Image:worm3.jpg|thumb|right|275px|A [[wormhole]]]]
{{main|Wormhole}}
''Wormholes'' are a hypothetical warped spacetime which are also permitted by the [[Einstein field equations]] of general relativity,<ref>{{cite book | last = Visser | first = Matt | authorlink = Matt Visser | title = Lorentzian Wormholes | publisher = Springer-Verlag | date= 1996 | pages = p. 100 | id = ISBN 1-56396-653-0}}</ref> although it would be impossible to travel through a wormhole unless it was what is known as a [[Wormhole#Traversable wormholes|traversable wormhole]].


A proposed time-travel machine using a traversable wormhole would (hypothetically) work in the following way: One end of the wormhole is accelerated to some significant fraction of the speed of light, perhaps with some advanced [[propulsion|propulsion system]], and then brought back to the point of origin. Alternatively, another way is to take one entrance of the wormhole and move it to within the gravitational field of an object that has higher gravity than the other entrance, and then return it to a position near the other entrance. For both of these methods, [[time dilation]] causes the end of the wormhole that has been moved to have aged less than the stationary end, as seen by an external observer; however, time connects differently ''through'' the wormhole than ''outside'' it, so that [[synchronized]] clocks at either end of the wormhole will always remain synchronized as seen by an observer passing through the wormhole, no matter how the two ends move around.<ref name="Thorne2">{{cite book | last = Thorne | first = Kip S. | authorlink = Kip Thorne | title = [[Black Holes and Time Warps]] | publisher = W. W. Norton | date= 1994 | pages = p. 502 | id = ISBN 0-393-31276-3}}</ref> This means that an observer entering the accelerated end would exit the stationary end when the stationary end was the same age that the accelerated end had been at the moment before entry; for example, if prior to entering the wormhole the observer noted that a clock at the accelerated end read a date of 2007 while a clock at the stationary end read 2012, then the observer would exit the stationary end when its clock also read 2007, a trip backwards in time as seen by other observers outside. One significant limitation of such a time machine is that it is only possible to go as far back in time as the initial creation of the machine;<ref name="Thorne3">{{cite book | last = Thorne | first = Kip S. | authorlink = Kip Thorne | title = [[Black Holes and Time Warps]] | publisher = W. W. Norton | date= 1994 | pages = p. 504 | id = ISBN 0-393-31276-3}}</ref> in essence, it is more of a path through time than it is a device that itself moves through time, and it would not allow the technology itself to be moved backwards in time. This could provide an alternative explanation for [[Stephen Hawking|Hawking]]'s observation: a time machine will be built someday, but has not yet been built, so the tourists from the future cannot reach this far back in time.
Despite her tenure as "Lady of the English", Matilda was never loved by the people of her native land, who found her too foreign and haughty.{{Fact|date=March 2008}} The citizens of London were particularly aggrieved by her financial demands. She spoke three languages: [[French language|French]], [[German language|German]], and [[Latin]]. Although she gave up hope of being crowned Queen in 1141, her name always preceded that of her son Henry, even after he became king. Matilda died at in Notre Dame du Pré near Rouen and was buried in the Abbey church of Bec-Hellouin, Normandy. Her body was transferred to the [[Rouen Cathedral]] in 1847; her [[epitaph]] reads: "''Great by Birth, Greater by Marriage, Greatest in her Offspring: Here lies Matilda, the daughter, wife, and mother of Henry''."


According to current theories on the nature of wormholes, construction of a traversable wormhole would require the existence of a substance with negative energy (often referred to as "[[exotic matter]]") . More technically, the wormhole spacetime requires a distribution of energy that violates various [[energy condition]]s, such as the null energy condition along with the weak, strong, and dominant energy conditions.<ref name="visserwormholes">{{cite book | last = Visser | first = Matt | authorlink = Matt Visser | title = Lorentzian Wormholes | publisher = Springer-Verlag | date= 1996 | pages = p. 101 | id = ISBN 1-56396-653-0}}</ref> However, it is known that quantum effects can lead to small measurable violations of the null energy condition,<ref name="visserwormholes" /> and many physicists believe that the required negative energy may actually be possible due to the [[Casimir effect]] in quantum physics.<ref name="casimir">{{cite web |url=http://www.npl.washington.edu/av/altvw69.html |title=NASA Goes FTL Part 1: Wormhole Physics |accessdate=2006-12-02 |author=Cramer, John G. |authorlink=John G. Cramer}}</ref> Although early calculations suggested a very large amount of negative energy would be required, later calculations showed that the amount of negative energy can be made arbitrarily small.<ref name="negative energy">{{cite journal | first=Matt | last=Visser | authorlink = Matt Visser | coauthors = Sayan Kar, Naresh Dadhich | title=Traversable wormholes with arbitrarily small energy condition violations | journal = [[Physical Review Letters]] | volume = 90 | year=2003 | pages = 201102.1–201102.4 | doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.90.201102}} {{arxiv | archive = gr-qc | id = 0301003}}</ref>
== Historical fiction ==
The civil war between supporters of Stephen and the supporters of Matilda has proven popular as a subject in historical fiction. Novels dealing with it include:
* [[Graham Shelby]], ''The Villains of the Piece'', (1972) (published in the US as ''The Oath and the Sword'');
* The ''[[Brother Cadfael]]'' series by [[Edith Pargeter|Ellis Peters]], and the TV series made from them starring Sir [[Derek Jacobi]];
* [[Jean Plaidy]], ''Passionate Enemies'', the third book of her Norman Trilogy;
* [[Sharon Penman]], ''When Christ and His Saints Slept'' tells the story of the civil war;
* Haley Elizabeth Garwood, '[http://www.haleyelizabethgarwood.com The Forgotten Queen]' (1997, IBSN 0-9659721-9-4);
*[[Ken Follett]], ''[[The Pillars of the Earth]]'';
* Ellen Jones, ''The Fatal Crown''(highly inaccurately, in [[romance novel]]-style).
Indeed, some romance-type historical novels go so far as to posit a love-affair between Matilda and Stephen.
The Janna Mysteries- Felicity Pullman Set during the civil war between Stephen and Matilda


In 1993, [[Matt Visser]] argued that the two mouths of a wormhole with such an induced clock difference could not be brought together without inducing quantum field and gravitational effects that would either make the wormhole collapse or the two mouths repel each other.<ref name="visser_1">{{cite journal | first = Matt | last = Visser | authorlink = Matt Visser | title = From wormhole to time machine: Comments on Hawking's Chronology Protection Conjecture | journal = [[Physical Review]] D | volume = 47 | year = 1993 | pages = 554–565 | doi = 10.1103/PhysRevD.47.554}} {{arxiv | archive = hep-th | id = 9202090}}</ref> Because of this, the two mouths could not be brought close enough for [[causality (physics)|causality]] violation to take place. However, in a 1997 paper, Visser hypothesized that a complex "[[Roman ring]]" (named after [[Tom Roman]]) configuration of an N number of wormholes arranged in a symmetric polygon could still act as a time machine, although he concludes that this is more likely a flaw in classical quantum gravity theory rather than proof that causality violation is possible.<ref name="visser_2">{{cite journal | first = Matt | last = Visser | authorlink = Matt Visser | title = Traversable wormholes: the Roman ring | journal = Physical Review D | volume = 55 | year = 1997 | pages = 5212–5214 | doi = 10.1103/PhysRevD.55.5212}} {{arxiv | archive = gr-qc | id = 9702043}}</ref>
Matilda has been played on screen by [[Martita Hunt]] in the film adaptation of [[Jean Anouilh]]'s play ''[[Becket (film)|Becket]]'' (1964) and by [[Brenda Bruce]] in the [[BBC]] TV series ''[[The Devil's Crown]]'' (1978).


===Other approaches based on general relativity===
==Ancestors==
Another approach involves a dense spinning cylinder usually referred to as a [[Tipler cylinder]], a GR solution discovered by [[Willem Jacob van Stockum]]<ref name="stockum">{{cite journal | first = Willem Jacob | last = van Stockum | authorlink = Willem Jacob van Stockum | url = http://www-lorentz.leidenuniv.nl/history/stockum/Proc_R_Soc_Edinb_57_135_1937.jpg | title = The Gravitational Field of a Distribution of Particles Rotating about an Axis of Symmetry | year = 1936 | journal = Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh}}</ref> in 1936 and [[Kornel Lanczos]]<ref name="lanczos">{{cite journal | first = Kornel | last = Lanczos | authorlink = Kornel Lanczos | doi = 10.1023/A:1010277120072 | title = On a Stationary Cosmology in the Sense of Einstein''s Theory of Gravitation | year = 1924, republished in 1997 | journal = General Relativity and Gravitation | publisher = Springland Netherlands | volume = 29 | issue = 3 | pages = 363–399}}</ref> in 1924, but not recognized as allowing closed timelike curves<ref name="Earman1">{{cite book | last = Earman | first = John | title = Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers, and Shrieks: Singularities and Acausalities in Relativistic Spacetimes | publisher = Oxford University Press |date= 1995 | pages = p. 21 | id = ISBN 0-19-509591-X}}</ref> until an analysis by [[Frank Tipler]]<ref name="tipler"> {{cite journal | first = Frank J | last = Tipler | authorlink = Frank J. Tipler | title = Rotating Cylinders and the Possibility of Global Causality Violation | journal = [[Physical Review]] D | volume = 9 | year = 1974 | pages = 2203 | doi = 10.1103/PhysRevD.9.2203}}</ref> in 1974. If a cylinder is infinitely long and spins fast enough about its long axis, then a spaceship flying around the cylinder on a spiral path could travel back in time (or forward, depending on the direction of its spiral). However, the density and speed required is so great that ordinary matter is not strong enough to construct it. A similar device might be built from a [[cosmic string]], but none are known to exist, and it does not seem to be possible to create a new cosmic string.
{| class="wikitable"

|+'''Matilda's ancestors in three generations'''
Physicist [[Robert Forward]] noted that a naïve application of general relativity to quantum mechanics suggests another way to build a time machine. A heavy atomic nucleus in a strong [[magnetic field]] would elongate into a cylinder, whose density and "spin" are enough to build a time machine. Gamma rays projected at it might allow information (not matter) to be sent back in time; however, he pointed out that until we have a single theory combining relativity and quantum mechanics, we will have no idea whether such speculations are nonsense.{{Fact|date=February 2007}}
|-

|-
A more fundamental objection to time travel schemes based on rotating cylinders or cosmic strings has been put forward by Stephen Hawking, who proved a theorem showing that according to general relativity it is impossible to build a time machine of a special type (a "time machine with the compactly generated Cauchy horizon") in a region where the [[weak energy condition]] is satisfied, meaning that the region contains no matter with negative energy density ([[exotic matter]]). Solutions such as Tipler's assume cylinders of infinite length, which are easier to analyze mathematically, and although Tipler suggested that a finite cylinder might produce closed timelike curves if the rotation rate were fast enough,<ref name="Earman2">{{cite book | last = Earman | first = John | title = Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers, and Shrieks: Singularities and Acausalities in Relativistic Spacetimes | publisher = Oxford University Press |date= 1995 | pages = p. 169 | id = ISBN 0-19-509591-X}}</ref> he did not prove this. But Hawking points out that because of his theorem, "it can't be done with positive energy density everywhere! I can prove that to build a finite time machine, you need negative energy."<ref name="futureofspacetime2">{{cite book | last = Hawking | first = Stephen | authorlink = Stephen Hawking | coauthors = [[Kip Thorne]], [[Igor Dmitriyevich Novikov|Igor Novikov]], [[Timothy Ferris]], [[Alan Lightman]] | title = The Future of Spacetime | publisher = W. W. Norton |date= 2002 | pages = p. 96 | id = ISBN 0-393-02022-3}}</ref> This result comes from Hawking's 1992 paper on the [[chronology protection conjecture]], where he examines "the case that the causality violations appear in a finite region of spacetime without curvature singularities" and proves that "[t]here will be a [[Cauchy horizon]] that is compactly generated and that in general contains one or more closed null geodesics which will be incomplete. One can define geometrical quantities that measure the Lorentz boost and area increase on going round these closed null geodesics. If the causality violation developed from a noncompact initial surface, the averaged weak energy condition must be violated on the Cauchy horizon."<ref name="chronology protection2">{{cite journal | first=Stephen | last=Hawking | authorlink = Stephen Hawking | url=http://link.aps.org/abstract/PRD/v46/p603 | title=Chronology protection conjecture | journal = Physical Review D | volume = 46 | year=1992 | pages = 603–611 | doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.46.603}}</ref> However, this theorem does not rule out the possibility of time travel 1) by means of time machines with the non-compactly generated Cauchy horizons (such as the Deutsch-Politzer time machine) and 2) in regions which contain exotic matter (which would be necessary for traversable wormholes or the [[Alcubierre drive]]). Because the theorem is based on general relativity, it is also conceivable a future theory of quantum gravity which replaced general relativity would allow time travel even without exotic matter (though it is also possible such a theory would place even more restrictions on time travel, or rule it out completely).
| rowspan="8" align="center"| '''Empress Matilda'''

| rowspan="4" align="center"| '''Father:'''<br />[[Henry I of England]]
===Time travel and the anthropic principle===
| rowspan="2" align="center"| '''Paternal Grandfather:'''<br />[[William I of England]]
It has been suggested by physicists such as [[Max Tegmark]] that the absence of time travel and the existence of [[causality (physics)|causality]] might be due to the [[anthropic principle]]. The argument is that a universe which allows for time travel and closed time-like loops is one in which intelligence could not evolve because it would be impossible for a being to sort events into a past and future or to make predictions or comprehend the world around them (at least, not if the time travel occurs in such a way that it disrupts that evolutionary process).{{Fact|date=February 2007}}
| align="center"| '''Paternal Great-grandfather:'''<br />[[Robert the Magnificent]]

|-
===Experiments carried out===
| align="center"| '''Paternal Great-grandmother:'''<br />[[Herleva]]
Certain experiments carried out during the last ten years give the impression of reversed [[causality]] but are interpreted in a different way by the scientific community. For example, in the [[delayed choice quantum eraser]] experiment performed by [[Marlan Scully]], pairs of [[Quantum entanglement|entangled]] [[photons]] are divided into "signal photons" and "idler photons", with the signal photons emerging from one of two locations and their position later measured as in the [[double slit experiment]], and depending on how the idler photon is measured, the experimenter can either learn which of the two locations the signal photon emerged from or "erase" that information. Even though the signal photons can be measured before the choice has been made about the idler photons, the choice seems to retroactively determine whether or not an [[interference pattern]] is observed when one correlates measurements of idler photons to the corresponding signal photons. However, since interference can only be observed after the idler photons are measured and they are correlated with the signal photons, there is no way for experimenters to tell what choice will be made in advance just by looking at the signal photons, and under most interpretations of quantum mechanics the results can be explained in a way that does not violate causality.
|-

| rowspan="2" align="center"| '''Paternal Grandmother:'''<br />[[Matilda of Flanders]]
The experiment of [[Lijun Wang]] might also give the appearance of causality violation since it made it possible to send packages of waves through a bulb of caesium gas in such a way that the package appeared to exit the bulb 62 nanoseconds before its entry. But a wave package is not a single well-defined object but rather a sum of multiple waves of different frequencies (''see'' [[Fourier analysis]]), and the package can appear to move faster than light or even backwards in time even if none of the pure waves in the sum do so. This effect cannot be used to send any matter, energy, or information backwards in time, so this experiment is understood not to violate causality either.
| align="center"| '''Paternal Great-grandfather:'''<br />[[Baldwin V, Count of Flanders]]

|-
The physicists [[Günter Nimtz]] and Alfons Stahlhofen, of the University of Koblenz, claim to have violated Einstein's theory of relativity by transmitting photons faster than the speed of light. They say they have conducted an experiment in which microwave photons - energetic packets of light - traveled "instantaneously" between a pair of prisms that had been moved up to {{convert|3|ft|m|abbr=on}} apart, using a phenomenon known as quantum tunneling. Nimtz told New Scientist magazine: "For the time being, this is the only violation of special relativity that I know of." However, other physicists say that this phenomenon does not allow information to be transmitted faster than light. Aephraim Steinberg, a quantum optics expert at the University of Toronto, Canada, uses the analogy of a train traveling from Chicago to New York, but dropping off train cars at each station along the way, so that the center of the train moves forward at each stop; in this way, the center of the train exceeds the speed of any of the individual cars.<ref name = "nimtz">{{Citation | last = Anderson | first = Mark | title=Light seems to defy its own speed limit | magazine = [[New Scientist]] | volume = 195 | issue = 2617 | pages= 10 | year = 2007 | date= August 18-24, 2007 | url = http://www.eurekalert.org/pub_releases/2007-08/ns-lst081607.php }}</ref>
| align="center"| '''Paternal Great-grandmother:'''<br />[[Adela of France, Countess of Flanders]]

|-
Some physicists have attempted to perform experiments which would show genuine causality violations, but so far without success. The Space-time Twisting by Light (STL) experiment run by physicist [[Ronald Mallett]] is attempting to observe a violation of causality when a neutron is passed through a circle made up of a laser whose path has been twisted by passing it through a [[photonic crystal]]. Mallett has some physical arguments which suggest that closed timelike curves would become possible through the center of a laser which has been twisted into a loop. However, other physicists dispute his arguments (''see'' [[Ronald Mallett#Objections|objections]]).
| rowspan="4" align="center"| '''Mother:'''<br />[[Matilda of Scotland]]

| rowspan="2" align="center"| '''Maternal Grandfather:'''<br />[[Malcolm III of Scotland]]
====Non-physics based experiments====
| align="center"| '''Maternal Great-grandfather:'''<br />[[Duncan I of Scotland]]
Several experiments have been carried out to try to entice future humans, who might invent time travel technology, to come back and demonstrate it to people of the present time. Events such as Perth's Destination Day (2005) or MIT's [[Time Traveler Convention]] heavily publicized permanent "advertisements" of a meeting time and place for future time travelers to meet. Back in 1982, a group in Baltimore, MD., identifying itself as the Krononauts, hosted an event of this type welcoming Visitors from the Futures. <ref>Franklin, Ben A. (March 11, 1982), [http://select.nytimes.com/gst/abstract.html?res=F70E13FD395F0C728DDDAA0894DA484D81 "The night the planets were aligned with Baltimore lunacy"], [[New York Times]].</ref> <ref>Goodman, Linda (1978). ''Linda Goodman's Love Signs'', Leo-Aquarius chap. Harper and Row. ISBN 978-0060968960.</ref><ref>MacAdams, Lewis (January, 1982), Wet Magazine.</ref><ref>[http://www.baltoco.org/wiki/Crater_Baltimore The Crater Baltimore Project]</ref> These experiments only stood the possibility of generating a positive result demonstrating the existence of time travel, but have failed so far—no time travelers are known to have attended either event. Although it is theoretically possible that future humans have traveled back in time, but have traveled back to the meeting time and place in a [[Multiverse|parallel universe]].<ref>[http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/0102010 [gr-qc/0102010&#93; Many worlds in one<!-- Bot generated title -->]</ref> Another factor is that for all the time travel devices considered under current physics (such as those that operate using [[wormhole]]s), it is impossible to travel back to before the time machine was actually made.<ref>[http://www.abc.net.au/science/slab/wormholes/default.htm Taking the Cosmic Shortcut - ABC Science Online<!-- Bot generated title -->]</ref><ref>[http://spaceplace.nasa.gov/en/educators/podcast/transcripts/071129_time_travel.shtml Transcript of interview with Dr. Marc Rayman at "Space Place"]</ref>
|-

| align="center"| '''Maternal Great-grandmother:'''<br />Suthen?
==Time travel to the future in physics==
|-
[[Image:Twin paradox Minkowski diagram.png|thumb|right|140px|[[Twin paradox]] diagram]]
| rowspan="2" align="center"| '''Maternal Grandmother:'''<br />[[Saint Margaret of Scotland]]
There are various ways in which a person could "travel into the future" in a limited sense: the person could set things up so that in a small amount of his own subjective time, a large amount of subjective time has passed for other people on Earth. For example, an observer might take a trip away from the Earth and back at [[special relativity|relativistic]] velocities, with the trip only lasting a few years according to the observer's own clocks, and return to find that thousands of years had passed on Earth. It should be noted, though, that according to relativity there is no objective answer to the question of how much time "really" passed during the trip; it would be equally valid to say that the trip had lasted only a few years or that the trip had lasted thousands of years, depending on your choice of [[Frame of reference|reference frame]].
| align="center"| '''Maternal Great-grandfather:'''<br />[[Edward the Exile]]

|-
This form of "travel into the future" is theoretically allowed using the following methods:<ref name="Gott" />
| align="center"| '''Maternal Great-grandmother:'''<br />[[Agatha, wife of Edward the Exile|Agatha]]
*Using time dilation under the [[Theory of Special Relativity]], for instance:
|}
**Traveling at almost the [[speed of light]] to a distant star, then slowing down, turning around, and traveling at almost the speed of light back to [[Earth]]<ref name="TimeTravelPBS">{{cite journal | first = | last = | | title = http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/time/thinktime.html | year = }} </ref> (see the [[Twin paradox]])
*Using time dilation under the [[Theory of General Relativity]], for instance:
**Residing inside of a hollow, high-mass object;
**Residing just outside of the event horizon of a [[black hole]], or on the surface of a larger-than-earth mass object.

Additionally, it might be possible to see the distant future of the Earth using methods which do not involve relativity at all, although it is even more debatable whether these should be deemed a form of "time travel":
*[[Hibernation]]
*[[Suspended animation]]

===Time dilation===
[[Image:Time dilation02.gif|thumb|right|180px|Transversal [[Time dilation]]]]
{{main|Time dilation}}
''Time dilation'' is permitted by [[Albert Einstein]]'s [[Special relativity|special]] and [[General relativity|general]] theories of relativity. These theories state that, relative to a given observer, time passes more slowly for bodies moving quickly relative to that observer, or bodies that are deeper within a [[gravity well]].<ref>Physics for Scientists and Engineers with Modern Physics, Fifth Edition, p.1258.</ref> For example, a clock which is moving relative to the observer will be measured to run slow in that observer's [[rest frame]]; as a clock approaches the speed of light it will almost slow to a stop, although it can never quite reach light speed so it will never completely stop. For two clocks moving [[Inertial frame of reference|inertially]] (not accelerating) relative to one another, this effect is reciprocal, with each clock measuring the other to be ticking slower. However, the symmetry is broken if one clock accelerates, as in the [[twin paradox]] where one twin stays on Earth while the other travels into space, turns around (which involves acceleration), and returns—in this case both agree the traveling twin has aged less. General relativity states that time dilation effects also occur if one clock is deeper in a gravity well than the other, with the clock deeper in the well ticking more slowly; this effect must be taken into account when calibrating the clocks on the satellites of the [[Global Positioning System]], and it could lead to significant differences in rates of aging for observers at different distances from a [[black hole]].

It has been calculated that, under general relativity, a person could travel forward in time at a rate four times that of distant observers by residing inside a spherical shell with a diameter of 5 meters and the mass of [[Jupiter]].<ref name="Gott">{{cite journal | first = J. Richard | last = Gott | title = Time Travel in Einstein's Universe | year = 2002}} p.76-140 </ref> For such a person, every one second of their "personal" time would correspond to four seconds for distant observers. Of course, squeezing the mass of a large planet into such a structure is not expected to be within our technological capabilities in the near future.

===Time perception===
Time perception can be apparently sped up for [[organism|living organisms]] through [[hibernation]], where the [[Thermoregulation|body temperature]] and [[metabolism|metabolic]] rate of the creature is reduced. A more extreme version of this is [[suspended animation]], where the rates of chemical processes in the subject would be severely reduced.

Time dilation and suspended animation only allow "travel" to the future, never the past, so they do not violate [[causality]], and arguably should not be considered time travel.

==Other ideas about time travel from mainstream physics==
===The possibility of paradoxes===<!-- This section is linked from [["All You Zombies—"]] -->
The [[Novikov self-consistency principle]] and recent calculations by [[Kip S. Thorne]]{{Fact|date=February 2007}} indicate that simple masses passing through time travel wormholes could never engender paradoxes&mdash;there are ''no'' initial conditions that lead to paradox once time travel is introduced. If his results can be generalized, they would suggest, curiously, that none of the supposed paradoxes formulated in time travel stories can actually be formulated at a precise physical level: that is, that ''any'' situation you can set up in a time travel story turns out to permit ''many'' [[consistent]] solutions. The circumstances might, however, turn out to be almost unbelievably strange.{{Fact|date=February 2007}}

Parallel universes might provide a way out of paradoxes. [[Hugh Everett|Everett's]] [[many-worlds interpretation]] of quantum mechanics suggests that all possible quantum events can occur in mutually exclusive histories.<ref name="many-worlds">{{cite web |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-manyworlds/ |title=Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics |accessdate=2006-10-28 |author=Vaidman, Lev }}</ref> These alternate, or parallel, histories would form a branching tree symbolizing all possible outcomes of any interaction. If all possibilities exist, any paradoxes could be explained by having the paradoxical events happening in a different universe. This concept is most often used in science-fiction, but some physicists such as [[David Deutsch]] have suggested that if time travel is possible and the many-worlds interpretation is correct, then a time traveler should indeed end up in a different history than the one he started from.<ref name="deutsch" /> On the other hand, [[Stephen Hawking]] has argued that even if the many-worlds interpretation is correct, we should expect each time traveler to experience a single self-consistent timeline, so that time travelers remain within their own world rather than traveling to a different one.<ref name="Hawking warp">{{cite web |url=http://www.hawking.org.uk/lectures/warps3.html |title=Space and Time Warps |accessdate=2006-11-20 |author=Hawking, Steven |format=html}}</ref>

[[Daniel Greenberger]] and [[Karl Svozil]] proposed that [[Quantum mechanics|quantum theory]] gives a model for time travel without paradoxes.<ref name="greenberger">{{cite journal | first = Daniel M | last = Greenberger | coauthors = Karl Svozil | title = Quantum Theory Looks at Time Travel | year = 2005}} {{arxiv | archive = quant-ph | id = 0506027}}</ref><ref>[http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/4097258.stm BBC News - New model 'permits time travel']</ref> In quantum theory observation causes possible states to 'collapse' into one measured state; hence, the past observed from the present is deterministic (it has only one possible state), but the present observed from the past has many possible states until our actions cause it to collapse into one state. Our actions will then be seen to have been inevitable.

===Using quantum entanglement===
Quantum-mechanical phenomena such as [[quantum teleportation]], the [[EPR paradox]], or [[quantum entanglement]] might appear to create a mechanism that allows for faster-than-light (FTL) communication or time travel, and in fact some interpretations of quantum mechanics such as the [[Bohm interpretation]] presume that some information is being exchanged between particles instantaneously in order to maintain correlations between particles.<ref name="Bohm">{{cite web |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-bohm/ |title=Bohmian Mechanics |accessdate=2006-10-30 |author=Goldstein, Sheldon }}</ref> This effect was referred to as "[[action at a distance (physics)#Quantum mechanics|spooky action at a distance]]" by Einstein.

Nevertheless, the fact that causality is preserved in quantum mechanics is a rigorous result in modern [[quantum field theory|quantum field theories]], and therefore modern theories do not allow for time travel or [[superluminal communication|FTL communication]]. In any specific instance where FTL has been claimed, more detailed analysis has proven that to get a signal, some form of classical communication must also be used.{{Fact|date=May 2008}} The [[no-communication theorem]] also gives a general proof that quantum entanglement cannot be used to transmit information faster than classical signals. The fact that these quantum phenomena apparently do ''not'' allow FTL time travel is often overlooked in popular press coverage of quantum teleportation experiments.{{Fact|date=May 2008}} How the rules of quantum mechanics work to preserve causality is an active area of research.{{Fact|date=May 2008}}

==Philosophic understandings of time travel==
{{Refimprove|section|date=May 2008}}
{{Expand|section|date=May 2008}}
The [[relativity of simultaneity]] in modern physics favors the [[philosophy|philosophic]] view known as [[four dimensionalism]] in which past, present and future events all coexist in a single spacetime. Block Universe theory, or [[Eternalism (philosophy of time)|eternalism]], builds on a standard method of modeling time as a dimension in physics, to give time a similar ontology to that of space. This would mean that time is just another dimension, that future events are "already there", and that there is no objective flow of time.

[[Presentism (philosophy of time)|Presentism]] is a school of philosophy that holds that neither the [[future]] nor the [[past]] exist, and there are no non-present objects. In this view, time travel is impossible because there is no future or past to travel to. However, some 21st century presentists have argued that although past and future objects do not exist, there can still be definite truths about past and future events, and thus it is possible that a future truth about a time traveler deciding to appear in the present could explain the time traveler's actual existence in the present.<ref name="Presentism">{{cite journal | first = Simon | last = Keller | coauthors = Michael Nelson | title = Presentists should believe in time-travel | url = http://people.bu.edu/stk/Papers/Timetravel.pdf | journal = Australian Journal of Philosophy | volume = 79.3 | pages = 333–345 | month = September | year = 2001 | doi = 10.1080/713931204}}</ref><ref name="Bourne">This view is contested by another contemporary advocate of presentism, Craig Bourne, in his recent book ''A Future for Presentism'', although for substantially different (and more complex) reasons.</ref>

==Ideas from fiction==
{{See|Time travel in fiction}}

===Types of time travel===
Time travel themes in [[science fiction]] and the media can generally be grouped into two main types and a third, less common type (based on effect&mdash;methods are extremely varied and numerous), each of which is further subdivided. These classifications do not address the issue of time travel itself, i.e. how to travel through time, but instead call to attention differing rules of the time line.

:1. The time line is consistent and can never be changed.
::1.1 One does not have full control of the time travel. One example of this is ''[[The Morphail Effect]]''. This concept of time can be referred to as circular causation. For examples of circular causation, see [[Robert A. Heinlein]]'s story ''[[By His Bootstraps]]''.
::1.2 The [[Novikov self-consistency principle]] applies (named after Dr. [[Igor Dmitrievich Novikov]], Professor of Astrophysics at [[Copenhagen University]]). The principle states that if you travel in time, you cannot act in such a way so as to create a paradox.
::1.3 Any event that appears to have changed a time line has instead created a new one. It has been suggested that travel to the past would create an entire new parallel universe where the traveler would be free from paradoxes since he/she is not from that universe<ref>"[http://www.soundedit.com.au/swaggers/paradox.html Time Travel and Resolving Paradoxes in Fiction]"</ref>.
:::1.3.1 Such an ''event'' can be the life line existence of a human (or other intelligence) such that manipulation of history ends up with there being more than one of the same individual, sometimes called ''time clones''.
:::1.3.2 The new time line might be a copy of the old one with changes caused by the time traveler. For example there is the ''Accumulative Audience Paradox'' where multitudes of time traveler tourists wish to attend some event in the life of [[Jesus]] or some other historical figure, where history tells us there were no such multitudes. Each tourist arrives in a reality that is a copy of ''the original'' with the added people, and no way for the tourist to travel back to ''the original'' time line.
:2. The time line is flexible and is subject to change.
::2.1 The time line is extremely change resistant and requires great effort to change it. Small changes will only alter the immediate future and events will conspire to maintain constant events in the far future; only large changes will alter events in the distant future. (Example: [[The Saga of Darren Shan]], where major events in the past cannot be changed, but minor events can be affected. This is explained as if you went back in time and killed [[Adolf Hitler|Hitler]], another [[Nazi]] would take his place and commit his same actions.)
::2.2 The time line is easily changed. (Example: [[Doctor Who]], where the time line is fluid and changes often naturally; even changes to the traveler's own timeline are possible, though it is suggested such an act would destroy most of the universe.)
:3. The time line is consistent, but only insofar as its consistency can be verified.
::3.1 The [[Novikov self-consistency principle]] applies, but if and only if it is verified to apply. Attempts to travel into the past to change events are possible, but provided that:
:::-They do not interfere with the occurrence of such an attempt in the present (as would be the case in the [[Grandfather Paradox]]), and
:::-The change is never ultimately verified to occur by the traveler (e.g. there is no possibility of returning to the present to witness the change).

There are also numerous science fiction stories allegedly about time travel that are not internally consistent, where the traveler makes all kinds of changes to some historical time, but we do not get to see any consequences of this in our present day.{{Fact|date=February 2007}}

====Immutable timelines====
Time travel in a type 1 universe does not allow any [[paradox]]es, although in 1.3, events can ''appear'' to be paradoxical.

In 1.1, time travel is constrained to prevent paradox. If one attempts to make a paradox, one undergoes involuntary or uncontrolled time travel. [[Michael Moorcock]] uses a form of this principle and calls it ''The Morphail Effect''. In the time-travel stories of [[Connie Willis]], time travelers encounter "slippage" which prevents them from either reaching the intended time or translates them a sufficient distance from their destination at the intended time, as to prevent any paradox from occurring.

:Example: A man who travels into the past with intentions to kill Hitler finds himself on a Montana farm in late April 1945.

In 1.2, the Novikov self-consistency principle asserts that the existence of a method of time travel constrains events to remain self-consistent (i.e. no paradoxes). This will cause any attempt to violate such consistency to fail, even if extremely improbable events are required.

:Example: You have a device that can send a single bit of information back to itself at a precise moment in time. You receive a bit at 10:00:00 p.m., then no bits for thirty seconds after that. If you send a bit back to 10:00:00 p.m., everything works fine. However, if you try to send a bit to 10:00:15 p.m. (a time at which no bit was received), your transmitter will mysteriously fail. Or your dog will distract you for fifteen seconds. Or your transmitter will appear to work, but as it turns out your receiver failed at exactly 10:00:15 p.m., etc. Examples of this kind of universe are found in ''[[Timemaster]]'', a novel by Dr. Robert Forward, the ''[[Twilight Zone]]'' episode "[[No Time Like the Past]]", and the 1980 [[Jeannot Szwarc]] film ''[[Somewhere in Time (film)|Somewhere In Time]]'' (based on [[Richard Matheson]]'s novel ''[[Bid Time Return]]'').

:An example which could conceivably fall into either 1.1 or 1.2 can be seen in book and film versions of ''[[Harry Potter and the Prisoner of Azkaban]]''. [[Harry Potter (character)|Harry]] went back in time with [[Hermione Granger|Hermione]] to change history. As they do so it becomes apparent that they are simply performing actions that were previously seen in the story, although neither the characters nor the reader were aware of the causes of those actions at the time. This is another example of the [[predestination paradox]]. It is arguable, however, that the mechanics of time travel actually prevented any paradoxes, firstly, by preventing them from realizing ''a priori'' that time travel was occurring and secondly, by enabling them to recall the precise action to take at the precise time and keep history consistent.

In 1.3, any event that appears to have caused a paradox has instead created a new time line. The old time line remains unchanged, with the time traveler or information sent simply having vanished, never to return. A difficulty with this explanation, however, is that conservation of mass-energy would be violated for the origin timeline and the destination timeline. A possible solution to this is to have the mechanics of time travel require that mass-energy be exchanged in precise balance between past and future at the moment of travel, or to simply expand the scope of the conservation law to encompass all timelines. Some examples of this kind of time travel can be found in [[David Gerrold]]'s book ''[[The Man Who Folded Himself]]'' and [[The Time Ships]] by [[Stephen baxter|Stephen Baxter]], plus several episodes of the TV show ''Star Trek: The Next Generation''.

====Mutable timelines====<!-- This section is linked from [[Back to the Future Part II]] -->
Time travel in a Type 2 universe is much more complex. The biggest problem is how to explain changes in the past. One method of explanation is that once the past changes, so too do the memories of all observers. This would mean that no observer would ever observe the changing of the past (because they will not remember changing the past). This would make it hard to tell whether you are in a Type 1 universe or a Type 2 universe. You could, however, infer such information by knowing if a) communication with the past were possible or b) it appeared that the time line had ''never'' been changed as a result of an action someone remembers taking, although evidence exists that other people are changing their time lines fairly often. An example of this kind of universe is presented in ''[[Thrice Upon a Time]]'', a novel by [[James P. Hogan (writer)|James P. Hogan]]. The [[Back to the Future trilogy]] films also seem to feature a single mutable timeline (see the [http://www.bttf.com/film_faq.htm Back to the Future FAQ] for details on how the writers imagined time travel worked in the movies' world). By contrast, the short story ''Brooklyn Project'' by [[William Tenn]] provides a sketch of life in a Type 2 world where no one even notices as the timeline changes repeatedly.

In type 2.1, attempts are being made at changing the timeline, however, all that is accomplished in the first tries is that the ''way'' of how decisive events happen is changed; final conclusions in the bigger scheme cannot be brought to a different outcome. Example: In the Movie [[Deja Vu (film)|Deja Vu]] a paper note is being sent to the past with vital information to prevent the main plot incident. All that happens, though, is that an ATF agent gets killed, with the final disaster still not being prevented; also, the very same agent died in the previous version of the timeline as well, albeit under different circumstances. Finally though, the timeline is changed (Claire Kuchever is being saved from murder) by sending a human back into the past in order to prevent the murder of Claire and the main incident (a terrorist attack), which is arguably a "stronger" measure than simply sending back a paper note.
:Similar to the [[Back to the Future trilogy|Back to the Future movie trilogy]], there seems to be a [[Ripple effect#Movies|ripple effect]] (changes from the past 'propagate' into the present, and people in the present have altered memory of events occurred after the changes made to the timeline)
:The type of timetravel in Deja Vu fits the 2.1 Type very well: Sending the paper note seems to be too "weak" a measure to cause any permanent effect, but agent Carlin going back into the past has a final decisive impact.

The science fiction writer [[Larry Niven]] suggests in his essay ''The Theory and Practice of Time Travel'' that in a type 2.1 universe, the most efficient way for the universe to "correct" a change is for time travel to never be discovered, and that in a type 2.2 universe, the very large (or infinite) number of time travelers from the endless future will cause the timeline to change wildly until it reaches a history in which time travel is never discovered. However, many other "stable" situations might also exist in which time travel occurs but no paradoxes are created; if the changeable-timeline universe finds itself in such a state no further changes will occur, and to the inhabitants of the universe it will appear identical to the type 1.2 scenario.{{Fact|date=February 2007}} This is sometimes referred to as the "Time Dilution Effect."

Few if any physicists or philosophers have taken seriously the possibility of "changing" the past except in the case of multiple universes, and in fact many have argued that this idea is logically incoherent,<ref>see [http://www.sfu.ca/philosophy/swartz/time_travel1.htm this discussion] between two philosophers, for example</ref> so the mutable timeline idea is rarely considered outside of science fiction.

Also, deciding whether a given universe is of Type 2.1 or 2.2 can not be done objectively, as the categorization of timeline-invasive measures as "strong" or "weak" is arbitrary, and up to interpretation: An observer can disagree about a measure being "weak", and might, in the lack of context, argue instead that simply a mishap occurred which then led to no effective change.

An example would be the papernote sent back to the past in the film Deja Vu, as described above: Was it a too "weak" change, or was it after all just (time-local; that is, in the past) bad circumstance which made it have no effect, but it might have worked if the paper note would have been sent back 1 hour earlier, or 1 hour later into the past? As the universe in Deja Vu seems to be not entirely self-preserving from paradoxes (some, arguably minute, paradoxes, do occur), both versions seem to be equally probable, to which the film gives no further clarification.

===Gradual and instantaneous===
In literature, there are two methods of time travel:

1. The most commonly used method of time travel in science fiction is the instantaneous movement from one point in time to another, like using the controls on a [[CD player]] to skip to a previous or next song, though in most cases, there is a machine of some sort, and some energy expended in order to make this happen (Like the time-traveling [[De Lorean DMC-12|De Lorean]] in ''[[Back to the Future]]'' or the [[phonebooth]] which traveled through the 'circuits of history' in ''[[Bill and Ted's Excellent Adventure]]''). In some cases, there is not even the beginning of a scientific explanation for this kind of time travel; it's popular probably because it is more spectacular and makes time travel easier. The "Universal Remote" used by [[Adam Sandler]] in the movie ''[[Click (film)|Click]]'' works in the same manner, although only in one direction, the future. While his character Michael Newman can travel back to a previous point it is merely a playback which he cannot interact with.

2. In ''[[The Time Machine]]'', [[H.G. Wells]] explains that we are moving through time with a constant speed. Time travel then is, in Wells' words, "stopping or accelerating one's drift along the time-dimension, or even turning about and traveling the other way." To expand on the audio playback analogy used above, this would be like rewinding or fast forwarding an analogue audio cassette and playing the tape at a chosen point. This method of gradual time travel is not as popular in modern science fiction. Perhaps the oldest example of this method of time travel is in [[Lewis Carroll]]'s ''[[Through the Looking-Glass]]'' (1871): the White Queen is living backwards, hence her memory is working both ways. Her kind of time travel is uncontrolled: she moves through time with a constant speed of -1 and she cannot change it. [[T.H. White]], in the first part of his Arthurian novel ''[[The Once and Future King]]'', ''[[The Sword in the Stone]]'' (1938) used the same idea: the wizard Merlyn lives back in time, because he was born "at the wrong end of time" and has to live backwards from in front. "Some people call it having second sight", he says.

===Time travel, or space-time travel?===
An objection that is sometimes raised against the concept of time machines in science fiction is that they ignore the motion of the Earth between the date the time machine departs and the date it returns. The idea that a traveler can go into a machine that sends him or her to 1865 and step out into the exact same spot on Earth might be said to ignore the issue that Earth is moving through space around the Sun, which is moving in the galaxy, and so on, so that advocates of this argument imagine that "realistically" the time machine should actually reappear in space far away from the Earth's position at that date. However, according to the [[theory of relativity]], this argument is based on a false premise. Relativity rejects the idea of [[absolute time and space]]; there can be no universal truth about the spatial distance between events which occurred at different times<ref name="Geroch">{{cite book | last = Geroch | first = Robert | title = General Relativity From A to B | publisher = The University of Chicago Press | date= 1978 | pages = 124}}</ref> (such as an event on Earth today and an event on Earth in 1865), and thus no objective truth about which point in space at one time is at the "same position" that the Earth was at another time. In the theory of [[special relativity]], which deals with situations where gravity is negligible, the laws of physics work the same way in every [[inertial frame of reference]] and therefore no frame's perspective is physically better than any other frame's, and different frames disagree about whether two events at different times happened at the "same position" or "different positions". In the theory of [[general relativity]], which incorporates the effects of gravity, ''all'' coordinate systems are on equal footing because of a feature known as "diffeomorphism invariance"<ref>[http://www.einstein-online.info/en/spotlights/background_independence/index.html Einstein Online: Actors on a changing stage]</ref> (also called [[general covariance]]).

Nevertheless, the idea that the Earth moves away from the time traveler when he takes a trip through time has been used in a few science fiction stories, such as the [[2000 AD (comic)|2000 AD]] comic ''Strontium Dog'', in which Johnny Alpha uses "Time Bombs" to propel an enemy several seconds into the future, during which time the movement of the Earth causes the unfortunate victim to re-materialize in space. Other science fiction stories try to anticipate this objection and offer a rationale for the fact that the traveler remains on Earth, such as the 1957 Robert Heinlein novel ''[[The Door into Summer]]'' where Heinlein essentially [[handwaving|handwaved]] the issue with a single sentence: "You stay on the [[world line]] you were on." In his 1980 novel ''[[The Number of the Beast (novel)|The Number of the Beast]]'' a "continua device" allows the protagonists to dial in the six (not four!) co-ordinates of space and time and it instantly moves them there&mdash;without explaining how such a device might work. The television series ''[[Seven Days (TV series)|Seven Days]]'' also dealt with this problem; when the chrononaut would be 'rewinding', he would also be propelling himself backwards around the earth's orbit, with the intention of landing at some chosen spatial location, though seldom hitting the mark precisely.{{Fact|date=February 2007}}<!-- Are citations really necessary for this kind of thing? I'd think any "fact" about the content of a referenced work of fiction could be verified by the fiction itself, so a citation is implied... --> In [[Piers Anthony]]'s ''[[Incarnations of Immortality#Bearing an Hourglass|Bearing an Hourglass]]'', the potent Hourglass of the [[Characters from the Incarnations of Immortality#Norton|Incarnation of Time]] naturally moves the Incarnation in space according to the numerous movements of the globe through the solar system, the solar system through the galaxy, etc.; but by carefully negating some of the movements he can also travel in space within the limits of the planet. The television series [[Doctor Who]] cleverly avoided this issue by establishing early on in the series that the Doctor's [[TARDIS]] is able to move about in space in addition to traveling in time.

==See also==
===Speculations===
*[[Grandfather paradox]]
*[[Predestination paradox]]
*[[Temporal paradox]]
*[[Tipler Cylinder]]
*[[Ronald Mallett]]

===Claims of time travel===
*[[Philadelphia Experiment]]
*[[Chronovisor]]
*[[Billy Meier]]
*[[Darren Daulton]]
*[[John Titor]]
*[[Moberly-Jourdain incident]]
*[[Montauk Project]]
*[[Time slip]]

===Fiction, humor===
*[[Andrew Carlssin]]
*[[Time travel in fiction]]
*[[Thiotimoline]]
*[[Time loop]]
*[[Chronodynamics]]


== Sources ==
* [[Gervase of Canterbury]]
* [[Robert of Torigny]]
* [[Roger of Hoveden]]
* [[Gesta Stephani]]
* [[Walter Map]]
* Bradbury, J. (1996) ''Stephen and Matilda: the Civil War of 1139-1153'', Sutton Publishing, ISBN 0-7509-0612-X
* Chibnall,Marjorie (1991) ''The Empress Matilda:Queen Consort, Queen Mother, and Lady of the English''
* Fletcher, John (1990) ''Sutton Courtenay: The History of a Thameside Village''
* Pain, Nesta (1978) ''Empress Matilda: Uncrowned Queen of England''
* Parsons, John Carmi. ''Medieval Mothering (New Middle Ages)'', sub. Marjorie Chibnall, "''Empress Matilda and Her Sons''"
* Gardener J and Wenborn W '' the History Today Companion to British History''
==References==
==References==
{{Reflist}}
{{reflist|2}}

{{start box}}
==Further reading==
{{s-hou|[[Dukes of Normandy|House of Normandy]]|February|1102|10 September|1167}}
* {{cite book | first = Paul | last = Davies | authorlink = Paul Davies | title = About Time | year = 1996 | publisher = Pocket Books | id = ISBN 0-684-81822-1}}
{{s-roy|de}}
* {{cite book | first = Paul | last = Davies | authorlink = Paul Davies | title = How to Build a Time Machine | year = 2002 | publisher = Penguin Books Ltd | id = ISBN 0-14-100534-3}}
{{succession box two to one | before1=[[Constanze of Sicily]] | before2=[[Eupraxia of Kiev]] | title1=[[List of Holy Roman Empresses and German queens|German Queen]] | years1=1114&ndash;1125 | title2=[[List of Holy Roman Empresses and German queens|Empress of the Holy Roman Empire]] | years2=1114&ndash;1125 | after=[[Richenza of Northeim]]}}
* {{cite book | first = Richard M | last = Gale | title = The Philosophy of Time | year = 1968 | id = ISBN 0-333-00042-0 | publisher = Palgrave Macmillan}}
{{s-reg|fr}}
* {{cite book | first = J. Richard | last = Gott | title = Time Travel in Einstein's Universe: The Physical Possibilities of Travel Through Time | id = ISBN 0-618-25735-7}}
{{s-bef|before=[[Melisende of Jerusalem|Melisende I of Jerusalem]]}}
* {{cite book | first = John | last = Gribbin | authorlink = John Gribbin | title = In Search of Schrödinger's Cat | year = 1985 | publisher = Corgi Adult | id = ISBN 0-552-12555-5}}
{{s-ttl|title=[[Count of Anjou|Countess consort of Anjou]]|years=[[1129]] - [[7 September]], [[1151]]}}
* {{cite journal | last = Miller | first = Kristie | title = Time travel and the open future | journal = Disputatio | volume = 1 | issue = 19 | year = 2005 | pages = 223–232}}
{{s-aft|after=[[Eleanor of Aquitaine]]}}
* {{cite book | first = Paul J. | last = Nahin | title = Time Machines: Time Travel in Physics, Metaphysics, and Science Fiction | year = 2001 | publisher = Springer-Verlag New York Inc. | id = ISBN 0-387-98571-9}}
{{s-roy|en}}
* Nahin, Paul J. (1997). ''Time Travel: A writer's guide to the real science of plausible time travel''. Writer's Digest Books. Cincinnati, Ohio. ISBN 0-89879-748-9
{{s-bef|before=[[William Adelin]]}}
* {{cite journal | first = H | last = Nikolic | title = Causal paradoxes: a conflict between relativity and the arrow of time}} {{arxiv|archive=gr-qc|id=0403121}}
{{s-ttl|title=[[List of heirs to the English and British thrones|Heir to the English Throne]]<br />''as [[heir presumptive|heiress presumptive]]'' |years=[[22 November]], [[1120]] (acknowledged 1127) - [[1 December]], [[1135]]}}
* {{cite book | first = Heinz | last = Pagels | authorlink = Heinz Pagels | title = Perfect Symmetry, the Search for the Beginning of Time | year = 1985 | publisher = Simon & Schuster | id = ISBN 0-671-46548-1}}
{{s-aft|after=[[Eustace IV of Boulogne]]}}
* {{cite book | first = Clifford | last = Pickover | authorlink = Clifford A. Pickover | title = Time: A Traveler's Guide | year = 1999 | publisher = Oxford University Press Inc, USA | id = ISBN 0-19-513096-0}}
{{s-pre}}
* {{cite book | first = Jenny | last = Randles | authorlink = Jenny Randles | title = Breaking the Time Barrier | year = 2005 | publisher = Simon & Schuster Ltd | id = ISBN 0-7434-9259-5}}
|-
* {{cite journal | first = Graham M | last = Shore | title = Constructing Time Machines | journal = Int. J. Mod. Phys. A, Theoretical}} {{arxiv|archive=gr-qc|id=0210048}}
{{s-bef | before=[[Henry I of England|Henry I]]}}
* {{cite book | first = David | last = Toomey | authorlink = David Toomey | title = The New Time Travelers: A Journey to the Frontiers of Physics | year = 2007 | publisher = W.W. Norton & Company | id = ISBN 978-0-393-06013-3}}
{{s-tul | title=&nbsp;[[Queen of England]]| years=1135–1167|reason=Crown claimed by [[Stephen of England|Stephen of Blois]]}}

{{s-non | reason=Gave up on the pretension in favour of son, [[Henry II of England]]}}
==External links==
{{end box}}
*[http://www.vega.org.uk/video/programme/61 Black holes, Wormholes and Time Travel] Freeview Lecture. A Royal Society Lecture by [[Paul Davies]] provided by the Vega Science Trust
{{English Monarchs}}
*[http://www.xibalba.demon.co.uk/jbr/chrono.html SF Chronophysics], a discussion of Time Travel as it relates to science fiction
{{DEFAULTSORT:Matilda, Empress}}
*[http://www.asimovs.com/_issue_0407/onthenet2.shtml On the Net: Time Travel] by James Patrick Kelly in ''Asimov's Science Fiction''
[[Category:1102 births]]
*[http://science.howstuffworks.com/time-travel.htm Howstuffworks' article on "How Time Travel Will Work"]
[[Category:1167 deaths]]
*[http://www.theory.caltech.edu/people/patricia/lctoc.html Time Travel in Flatland?]
[[Category:Anglo-Normans]]
*[http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/time NOVA Online: Time Travel]
[[Category:English and British princesses]]
*[http://www.physorg.com/news63371210.html Professor Predicts Human Time Travel This Century] [[Ronald Mallett]], Professor at the University of Connecticut, has used Einstein’s equations to design an experiment to observe a time traveling neutron in a circulating light beam. He published his research in ''Physics Letters''.
[[Category:Female regents]]
*[http://www.americanantigravity.com/articles/552/1/ Through The Looking Glass: Time-Travel in Brane Theory] An interview with a University of Hawaii research team seeking reverse-time communications using sterile neutrinos
[[Category:German queens consort]]
*[http://web.mit.edu/adorai/timetraveler Time Traveler Convention], at [[MIT]] - "Technically, you would only need one..."
[[Category:Holy Roman Empresses]]
*[http://www.math.siu.edu/Kocik/tm/tm-all-ch.htm Time Machines in Physics] - almost 200 citations from 1937 through 2001
[[Category:Heirs to the English and British thrones]]
*Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
[[Category:People from Winchester]]
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/time-machine/ Time Machines]
[[Category:People from Sutton Courtenay]]
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/time-travel-phys/ Time Travel and Modern Physics]
[[Category:Queens regnant of England]]
*Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
[[Category:Salian Dynasty]]
**[http://www.iep.utm.edu/t/time.htm Time]
[[Category:Women of medieval England]]
**[http://www.iep.utm.edu/t/timetrav.htm Time Travel]
[[Category:Women of medieval France]]
*Aparta Krystian. [http://www.timetravel.110mb.com Conventional Models of Time and Their Extensions in Science Fiction] A master's thesis exploring [[conceptual blending]] in time travel.
[[Category:Women of medieval Germany]]
*[http://www.telegraph.co.uk/earth/main.jhtml?xml=/earth/2008/02/06/scitime106.xml Time travellers from the future 'could be here in weeks'] Two mathematicians suggest that the [[Large Hadron Collider]] might create tiny [[wormhole]]s that could allow time travel
[[bs:Matilda Engleska]]
{{Time Topics}}
[[bg:Мод]]

[[cs:Matylda Anglická]]
[[Category:Philosophy of physics]]
[[cy:Yr Ymerodres Matilda]]
[[Category:Time travel|*]]
[[de:Mathilde von England (1102–1167)]]
[[Category:Time]]
[[et:Keisrinna Matilda]]

[[el:Αυτοκράτειρα Ματίλδη]]
{{Link FA|es}}
[[es:Matilde de Inglaterra]]
[[ar:سفر عبر الزمن]]
[[fr:Mathilde l'Emperesse]]
[[bg:Пътуване във времето]]
[[hr:Matilda]]
[[ca:Viatge en el temps]]
[[it:Imperatrice Matilde]]
[[cs:Cestování v čase]]
[[he:מתילדה הקיסרית]]
[[da:Tidsrejse]]
[[ka:მატილდა (ინგლისი)]]
[[de:Zeitreise]]
[[hu:Matild császárné]]
[[et:Ajaränd]]
[[nl:Mathildis van Engeland]]
[[es:Viaje a través del tiempo]]
[[ja:マティルダ (神聖ローマ皇后)]]
[[no:Maud av England]]
[[fr:Voyage dans le temps]]
[[pl:Matylda (cesarzowa)]]
[[io:Voyajo en tempo]]
[[id:Perjalanan waktu]]
[[pt:Matilde de Inglaterra]]
[[it:Viaggio nel tempo]]
[[ru:Матильда (королева Англии)]]
[[simple:Empress Matilda]]
[[he:מסע בזמן]]
[[sk:Cisárovná Maud]]
[[hu:Időutazás]]
[[fi:Matilde]]
[[nl:Tijdreizen]]
[[ja:タイムトラベル]]
[[sv:Matilda av England]]
[[no:Tidsreise]]
[[th:สมเด็จพระจักรพรรดินีมาทิลดา]]
[[pl:Podróżowanie w czasie]]
[[zh:马蒂尔达皇后]]
[[pt:Viagem no tempo]]
[[ru:Путешествия во времени]]
[[sr:Путовање кроз време]]
[[fi:Aikamatkustus]]
[[sv:Tidsresa]]
[[th:ไทม์แมชชีน]]
[[vi:Du hành thời gian]]
[[tr:Zamanda yolculuk]]
[[ur:سفرالوقت]]
[[zh:时间旅行]]

Revision as of 17:30, 10 October 2008

This article details time travel itself. For other uses, see Time Traveler.
Unsolved problem in physics:

Is time travel theoretically and practically possible? If so, how can paradoxes such as the grandfather paradox be avoided?

Time travel is the concept of moving between different moments in time in a manner analogous to moving between different points in space, either sending objects (or in some cases just information) backwards in time to a moment before the present, or sending objects forward from the present to the future without the need to experience the intervening period (at least not at the normal rate). Some interpretations of time travel also suggest that an attempt to travel backwards in time might take one to a parallel universe whose history would begin to diverge from the traveler's original history after the moment the traveler arrived in the past.[1] Although time travel has been a common plot device in fiction since the 19th century, and one-way travel into the future is arguably possible given the phenomenon of time dilation based on velocity in the theory of special relativity (exemplified by the twin paradox) as well as gravitational time dilation in the theory of general relativity, it is currently unknown whether the laws of physics would allow backwards time travel. Any technological device, whether fictional or hypothetical, that is used to achieve two-way time travel is known as a time machine.

Origins of the concept

There is no widespread agreement as to which written work should be recognized as the earliest example of a time travel story, since a number of early works feature elements ambiguously suggestive of time travel. For example, Memoirs of the Twentieth Century (1733) by Samuel Madden is mainly a series of letters from English ambassadors in various countries to the British "Lord High Treasurer", along with a few replies from the British Foreign Office, all purportedly written in 1997 and 1998 and describing the conditions of that era.[2] However, the framing story is that these letters were actual documents given to the narrator by his guardian angel one night in 1728; for this reason, Paul Alkon suggests in his book Origins of Futuristic Fiction that "the first time-traveler in English literature is a guardian angel who returns with state documents from 1998 to the year 1728",[3] although the book does not explicitly show how the angel obtained these documents. Alkon later qualifies this by writing "It would be stretching our generosity to praise Madden for being the first to show a traveler arriving from the future", but also says that Madden "deserves recognition as the first to toy with the rich idea of time-travel in the form of an artifact sent backwards from the future to be discovered in the present."[2]

Louis-Sébastien Mercier's L'An 2440, rêve s'il en fût jamais ("The Year 2440: A Dream If Ever There Were One") is a utopian novel set in the year 2440. An extremely popular work (it went through twenty-five editions after its first appearance in 1771), the work describes the adventures of an unnamed man, who, after engaging in a heated discussion with a philosopher friend about the injustices of Paris, falls asleep and finds himself in a Paris of the future. Robert Darnton writes that "despite its self-proclaimed character of fantasy...L'An 2440 demanded to be read as a serious guidebook to the future." [Robert Darnton, The Forbidden Best-Sellers of Pre-Revolutionary France (New York: W.W. Norton, 1996), 120.]

In the science fiction anthology Far Boundaries (1951), the editor August Derleth identifies the short story "Missing One's Coach: An Anachronism", written for the Dublin Literary Magazine by an anonymous author in 1838, as a very early time travel story.[4] In this story, the narrator is waiting under a tree to be picked up by a coach which will take him out of Newcastle, when he suddenly finds himself transported back over a thousand years, where he encounters the Venerable Bede in a monastery, and gives him somewhat ironic explanations of the developments of the coming centuries. It is never entirely clear whether these events actually occurred or were merely a dream — the narrator says that when he initially found a comfortable-looking spot in the roots of the tree, he sat down, "and as my sceptical reader will tell me, nodded and slept", but then says that he is "resolved not to admit" this explanation. A number of dreamlike elements of the story may suggest otherwise to the reader, such as the fact that none of the members of the monastery seem to be able to see him at first, and the abrupt ending where Bede has been delayed talking to the narrator and so the other monks burst in thinking that some harm has come to him, and suddenly the narrator finds himself back under the tree in the present (August of 1837), with his coach having just passed his spot on the road, leaving him stranded in Newcastle for another night.[5]

Charles Dickens' 1843 book A Christmas Carol is considered by some[6] to be one of the first depictions of time travel, as the main character, Ebenezer Scrooge, is transported to Christmases past, present and yet to come. These might be considered mere visions rather than actual time travel, though, since Scrooge only viewed each time period passively, unable to interact with them.

A clearer example of time travel is found in the popular 1861 book Paris avant les hommes (Paris before Men) by the French botanist and geologist Pierre Boitard, published posthumously. In this story the main character is transported into the prehistoric past by the magic of a "lame demon" (a French pun on Boitard's name), where he encounters such extinct animals as a Plesiosaur, as well as Boitard's imagined version of an apelike human ancestor, and is able to actively interact with some of them.[7] Another clear early example of time travel in fiction is the short story Template:PDFlink by Edward Page Mitchell, which appeared in the New York Sun in 1881. Mark Twain's A Connecticut Yankee in King Arthur's Court (1889), in which the protagonist finds himself in the time of King Arthur after a fight in which he is hit with a sledge hammer, was another early time travel story which helped bring the concept to a wide audience, and was also one of the first stories to show history being changed by the time traveler's actions.

The first time travel story to feature time travel by means of a time machine was Enrique Gaspar y Rimbau's 1887 book El Anacronópete.[8] This idea gained popularity with the H. G. Wells story The Time Machine, published in 1895 (preceded by a less influential story of time travel Wells wrote in 1888, titled The Chronic Argonauts), which also featured a time machine and which is often seen as an inspiration for all later science fiction stories featuring time travel.

Since that time, both science and fiction (see Time travel in fiction) have expanded on the concept of time travel, but whether it could be possible in reality is still an open question.

Time travel in theory

Some theories, most notably special and general relativity, suggest that suitable geometries of spacetime, or specific types of motion in space, might allow time travel into the past and future if these geometries or motions are possible.[9] In technical papers physicists generally avoid the commonplace language of "moving" or "traveling" through time ('movement' normally refers only to a change in spatial position as the time coordinate is varied), and instead discuss the possibility of closed timelike curves, which are worldlines that form closed loops in spacetime, allowing objects to return to their own past. There are known to be solutions to the equations of general relativity that describe spacetimes which contain closed timelike curves[citation needed], but the physical plausibility of these solutions is uncertain.

Physicists take for granted that if one were to move away from the Earth at relativistic velocities and return, more time would have passed on Earth than for the traveler, so in this sense it is accepted that relativity allows "travel into the future" (although according to relativity there is no single objective answer to how much time has 'really' passed between the departure and the return). On the other hand, many in the scientific community believe that backwards time travel is highly unlikely. Any theory which would allow time travel would require that issues of causality be resolved. The classic example of a problem involving causality is the "grandfather paradox": what if one were to go back in time and kill one's own grandfather before one's father was conceived? But some scientists believe that paradoxes can be avoided, either by appealing to the Novikov self-consistency principle or to the notion of branching parallel universes (see the possibility of paradoxes below).

Tourism in time

Stephen Hawking once suggested that the absence of tourists from the future constitutes an argument against the existence of time travel—a variant of the Fermi paradox. Of course this would not prove that time travel is physically impossible, since it might be that time travel is physically possible but that it is never in fact developed (or is cautiously never used); and even if it is developed, Hawking notes elsewhere that time travel might only be possible in a region of spacetime that is warped in the right way, and that if we cannot create such a region until the future, then time travelers would not be able to travel back before that date, so "This picture would explain why we haven't been over run by tourists from the future."[10] Carl Sagan also once suggested the possibility that time travelers could be here, but are disguising their existence or are not recognized as time travelers.[11]

General relativity

However, the theory of general relativity does suggest scientific grounds for thinking backwards time travel could be possible in certain unusual scenarios, although arguments from semiclassical gravity suggest that when quantum effects are incorporated into general relativity, these loopholes may be closed.[12] These semiclassical arguments led Hawking to formulate the chronology protection conjecture, suggesting that the fundamental laws of nature prevent time travel,[13] but physicists cannot come to a definite judgment on the issue without a theory of quantum gravity to join quantum mechanics and general relativity into a completely unified theory.[14]

Time travel to the past in physics

Time travel to the past is theoretically allowed using the following methods:[15]

The equivalence of time travel and faster-than-light travel

If one were able to move information or matter from one point to another faster than light, then according to special relativity, there would be some inertial frame of reference in which the signal or object was moving backwards in time. This is a consequence of the relativity of simultaneity in special relativity, which says that in some cases different reference frames will disagree on whether two events at different locations happened "at the same time" or not, and they can also disagree on the order of the two events (technically, these disagreements occur when spacetime interval between the events is 'space-like', meaning that neither event lies in the future light cone of the other).[16] If one of the two events represents the sending of a signal from one location and the second event represents the reception of the same signal at another location, then as long as the signal is moving at the speed of light or slower, the mathematics of simultaneity ensures that all reference frames agree that the transmission-event happened before the reception-event.[16] However, in the case of a hypothetical signal moving faster than light, there would always be some frames in which the signal was received before it was sent, so that the signal could be said to have moved backwards in time. And since one of the two fundamental postulates of special relativity says that the laws of physics should work the same way in every inertial frame, then if it is possible for signals to move backwards in time in any one frame, it must be possible in all frames. This means that if observer A sends a signal to observer B which moves FTL (faster than light) in A's frame but backwards in time in B's frame, and then B sends a reply which moves FTL in B's frame but backwards in time in A's frame, it could work out that A receives the reply before sending the original signal, a clear violation of causality in every frame. An illustration of such a scenario using spacetime diagrams can be found here.

According to special relativity it would take an infinite amount of energy to accelerate a slower-than-light object to the speed of light, and although relativity does not forbid the theoretical possibility of tachyons which move faster than light at all times, when analyzed using quantum field theory it seems that it would not actually be possible to use them to transmit information faster than light,[17] and there is no evidence for their existence.

Special spacetime geometries

The general theory of relativity extends the special theory to cover gravity, illustrating it in terms of curvature in spacetime caused by mass-energy and the flow of momentum. General relativity describes the universe under a system of field equations, and there exist solutions to these equations that permit what are called "closed time-like curves," and hence time travel into the past.[9]The first of these was proposed by Kurt Gödel, a solution known as the Gödel metric, but his (and many others') example requires the universe to have physical characteristics that it does not appear to have.[9] Whether general relativity forbids closed time-like curves for all realistic conditions is unknown .

Using wormholes

File:Worm3.jpg
A wormhole

Wormholes are a hypothetical warped spacetime which are also permitted by the Einstein field equations of general relativity,[18] although it would be impossible to travel through a wormhole unless it was what is known as a traversable wormhole.

A proposed time-travel machine using a traversable wormhole would (hypothetically) work in the following way: One end of the wormhole is accelerated to some significant fraction of the speed of light, perhaps with some advanced propulsion system, and then brought back to the point of origin. Alternatively, another way is to take one entrance of the wormhole and move it to within the gravitational field of an object that has higher gravity than the other entrance, and then return it to a position near the other entrance. For both of these methods, time dilation causes the end of the wormhole that has been moved to have aged less than the stationary end, as seen by an external observer; however, time connects differently through the wormhole than outside it, so that synchronized clocks at either end of the wormhole will always remain synchronized as seen by an observer passing through the wormhole, no matter how the two ends move around.[19] This means that an observer entering the accelerated end would exit the stationary end when the stationary end was the same age that the accelerated end had been at the moment before entry; for example, if prior to entering the wormhole the observer noted that a clock at the accelerated end read a date of 2007 while a clock at the stationary end read 2012, then the observer would exit the stationary end when its clock also read 2007, a trip backwards in time as seen by other observers outside. One significant limitation of such a time machine is that it is only possible to go as far back in time as the initial creation of the machine;[20] in essence, it is more of a path through time than it is a device that itself moves through time, and it would not allow the technology itself to be moved backwards in time. This could provide an alternative explanation for Hawking's observation: a time machine will be built someday, but has not yet been built, so the tourists from the future cannot reach this far back in time.

According to current theories on the nature of wormholes, construction of a traversable wormhole would require the existence of a substance with negative energy (often referred to as "exotic matter") . More technically, the wormhole spacetime requires a distribution of energy that violates various energy conditions, such as the null energy condition along with the weak, strong, and dominant energy conditions.[21] However, it is known that quantum effects can lead to small measurable violations of the null energy condition,[21] and many physicists believe that the required negative energy may actually be possible due to the Casimir effect in quantum physics.[22] Although early calculations suggested a very large amount of negative energy would be required, later calculations showed that the amount of negative energy can be made arbitrarily small.[23]

In 1993, Matt Visser argued that the two mouths of a wormhole with such an induced clock difference could not be brought together without inducing quantum field and gravitational effects that would either make the wormhole collapse or the two mouths repel each other.[24] Because of this, the two mouths could not be brought close enough for causality violation to take place. However, in a 1997 paper, Visser hypothesized that a complex "Roman ring" (named after Tom Roman) configuration of an N number of wormholes arranged in a symmetric polygon could still act as a time machine, although he concludes that this is more likely a flaw in classical quantum gravity theory rather than proof that causality violation is possible.[25]

Other approaches based on general relativity

Another approach involves a dense spinning cylinder usually referred to as a Tipler cylinder, a GR solution discovered by Willem Jacob van Stockum[26] in 1936 and Kornel Lanczos[27] in 1924, but not recognized as allowing closed timelike curves[28] until an analysis by Frank Tipler[29] in 1974. If a cylinder is infinitely long and spins fast enough about its long axis, then a spaceship flying around the cylinder on a spiral path could travel back in time (or forward, depending on the direction of its spiral). However, the density and speed required is so great that ordinary matter is not strong enough to construct it. A similar device might be built from a cosmic string, but none are known to exist, and it does not seem to be possible to create a new cosmic string.

Physicist Robert Forward noted that a naïve application of general relativity to quantum mechanics suggests another way to build a time machine. A heavy atomic nucleus in a strong magnetic field would elongate into a cylinder, whose density and "spin" are enough to build a time machine. Gamma rays projected at it might allow information (not matter) to be sent back in time; however, he pointed out that until we have a single theory combining relativity and quantum mechanics, we will have no idea whether such speculations are nonsense.[citation needed]

A more fundamental objection to time travel schemes based on rotating cylinders or cosmic strings has been put forward by Stephen Hawking, who proved a theorem showing that according to general relativity it is impossible to build a time machine of a special type (a "time machine with the compactly generated Cauchy horizon") in a region where the weak energy condition is satisfied, meaning that the region contains no matter with negative energy density (exotic matter). Solutions such as Tipler's assume cylinders of infinite length, which are easier to analyze mathematically, and although Tipler suggested that a finite cylinder might produce closed timelike curves if the rotation rate were fast enough,[30] he did not prove this. But Hawking points out that because of his theorem, "it can't be done with positive energy density everywhere! I can prove that to build a finite time machine, you need negative energy."[31] This result comes from Hawking's 1992 paper on the chronology protection conjecture, where he examines "the case that the causality violations appear in a finite region of spacetime without curvature singularities" and proves that "[t]here will be a Cauchy horizon that is compactly generated and that in general contains one or more closed null geodesics which will be incomplete. One can define geometrical quantities that measure the Lorentz boost and area increase on going round these closed null geodesics. If the causality violation developed from a noncompact initial surface, the averaged weak energy condition must be violated on the Cauchy horizon."[32] However, this theorem does not rule out the possibility of time travel 1) by means of time machines with the non-compactly generated Cauchy horizons (such as the Deutsch-Politzer time machine) and 2) in regions which contain exotic matter (which would be necessary for traversable wormholes or the Alcubierre drive). Because the theorem is based on general relativity, it is also conceivable a future theory of quantum gravity which replaced general relativity would allow time travel even without exotic matter (though it is also possible such a theory would place even more restrictions on time travel, or rule it out completely).

Time travel and the anthropic principle

It has been suggested by physicists such as Max Tegmark that the absence of time travel and the existence of causality might be due to the anthropic principle. The argument is that a universe which allows for time travel and closed time-like loops is one in which intelligence could not evolve because it would be impossible for a being to sort events into a past and future or to make predictions or comprehend the world around them (at least, not if the time travel occurs in such a way that it disrupts that evolutionary process).[citation needed]

Experiments carried out

Certain experiments carried out during the last ten years give the impression of reversed causality but are interpreted in a different way by the scientific community. For example, in the delayed choice quantum eraser experiment performed by Marlan Scully, pairs of entangled photons are divided into "signal photons" and "idler photons", with the signal photons emerging from one of two locations and their position later measured as in the double slit experiment, and depending on how the idler photon is measured, the experimenter can either learn which of the two locations the signal photon emerged from or "erase" that information. Even though the signal photons can be measured before the choice has been made about the idler photons, the choice seems to retroactively determine whether or not an interference pattern is observed when one correlates measurements of idler photons to the corresponding signal photons. However, since interference can only be observed after the idler photons are measured and they are correlated with the signal photons, there is no way for experimenters to tell what choice will be made in advance just by looking at the signal photons, and under most interpretations of quantum mechanics the results can be explained in a way that does not violate causality.

The experiment of Lijun Wang might also give the appearance of causality violation since it made it possible to send packages of waves through a bulb of caesium gas in such a way that the package appeared to exit the bulb 62 nanoseconds before its entry. But a wave package is not a single well-defined object but rather a sum of multiple waves of different frequencies (see Fourier analysis), and the package can appear to move faster than light or even backwards in time even if none of the pure waves in the sum do so. This effect cannot be used to send any matter, energy, or information backwards in time, so this experiment is understood not to violate causality either.

The physicists Günter Nimtz and Alfons Stahlhofen, of the University of Koblenz, claim to have violated Einstein's theory of relativity by transmitting photons faster than the speed of light. They say they have conducted an experiment in which microwave photons - energetic packets of light - traveled "instantaneously" between a pair of prisms that had been moved up to 3 ft (0.91 m) apart, using a phenomenon known as quantum tunneling. Nimtz told New Scientist magazine: "For the time being, this is the only violation of special relativity that I know of." However, other physicists say that this phenomenon does not allow information to be transmitted faster than light. Aephraim Steinberg, a quantum optics expert at the University of Toronto, Canada, uses the analogy of a train traveling from Chicago to New York, but dropping off train cars at each station along the way, so that the center of the train moves forward at each stop; in this way, the center of the train exceeds the speed of any of the individual cars.[33]

Some physicists have attempted to perform experiments which would show genuine causality violations, but so far without success. The Space-time Twisting by Light (STL) experiment run by physicist Ronald Mallett is attempting to observe a violation of causality when a neutron is passed through a circle made up of a laser whose path has been twisted by passing it through a photonic crystal. Mallett has some physical arguments which suggest that closed timelike curves would become possible through the center of a laser which has been twisted into a loop. However, other physicists dispute his arguments (see objections).

Non-physics based experiments

Several experiments have been carried out to try to entice future humans, who might invent time travel technology, to come back and demonstrate it to people of the present time. Events such as Perth's Destination Day (2005) or MIT's Time Traveler Convention heavily publicized permanent "advertisements" of a meeting time and place for future time travelers to meet. Back in 1982, a group in Baltimore, MD., identifying itself as the Krononauts, hosted an event of this type welcoming Visitors from the Futures. [34] [35][36][37] These experiments only stood the possibility of generating a positive result demonstrating the existence of time travel, but have failed so far—no time travelers are known to have attended either event. Although it is theoretically possible that future humans have traveled back in time, but have traveled back to the meeting time and place in a parallel universe.[38] Another factor is that for all the time travel devices considered under current physics (such as those that operate using wormholes), it is impossible to travel back to before the time machine was actually made.[39][40]

Time travel to the future in physics

Twin paradox diagram

There are various ways in which a person could "travel into the future" in a limited sense: the person could set things up so that in a small amount of his own subjective time, a large amount of subjective time has passed for other people on Earth. For example, an observer might take a trip away from the Earth and back at relativistic velocities, with the trip only lasting a few years according to the observer's own clocks, and return to find that thousands of years had passed on Earth. It should be noted, though, that according to relativity there is no objective answer to the question of how much time "really" passed during the trip; it would be equally valid to say that the trip had lasted only a few years or that the trip had lasted thousands of years, depending on your choice of reference frame.

This form of "travel into the future" is theoretically allowed using the following methods:[15]

Additionally, it might be possible to see the distant future of the Earth using methods which do not involve relativity at all, although it is even more debatable whether these should be deemed a form of "time travel":

Time dilation

Transversal Time dilation

Time dilation is permitted by Albert Einstein's special and general theories of relativity. These theories state that, relative to a given observer, time passes more slowly for bodies moving quickly relative to that observer, or bodies that are deeper within a gravity well.[42] For example, a clock which is moving relative to the observer will be measured to run slow in that observer's rest frame; as a clock approaches the speed of light it will almost slow to a stop, although it can never quite reach light speed so it will never completely stop. For two clocks moving inertially (not accelerating) relative to one another, this effect is reciprocal, with each clock measuring the other to be ticking slower. However, the symmetry is broken if one clock accelerates, as in the twin paradox where one twin stays on Earth while the other travels into space, turns around (which involves acceleration), and returns—in this case both agree the traveling twin has aged less. General relativity states that time dilation effects also occur if one clock is deeper in a gravity well than the other, with the clock deeper in the well ticking more slowly; this effect must be taken into account when calibrating the clocks on the satellites of the Global Positioning System, and it could lead to significant differences in rates of aging for observers at different distances from a black hole.

It has been calculated that, under general relativity, a person could travel forward in time at a rate four times that of distant observers by residing inside a spherical shell with a diameter of 5 meters and the mass of Jupiter.[15] For such a person, every one second of their "personal" time would correspond to four seconds for distant observers. Of course, squeezing the mass of a large planet into such a structure is not expected to be within our technological capabilities in the near future.

Time perception

Time perception can be apparently sped up for living organisms through hibernation, where the body temperature and metabolic rate of the creature is reduced. A more extreme version of this is suspended animation, where the rates of chemical processes in the subject would be severely reduced.

Time dilation and suspended animation only allow "travel" to the future, never the past, so they do not violate causality, and arguably should not be considered time travel.

Other ideas about time travel from mainstream physics

The possibility of paradoxes

The Novikov self-consistency principle and recent calculations by Kip S. Thorne[citation needed] indicate that simple masses passing through time travel wormholes could never engender paradoxes—there are no initial conditions that lead to paradox once time travel is introduced. If his results can be generalized, they would suggest, curiously, that none of the supposed paradoxes formulated in time travel stories can actually be formulated at a precise physical level: that is, that any situation you can set up in a time travel story turns out to permit many consistent solutions. The circumstances might, however, turn out to be almost unbelievably strange.[citation needed]

Parallel universes might provide a way out of paradoxes. Everett's many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics suggests that all possible quantum events can occur in mutually exclusive histories.[43] These alternate, or parallel, histories would form a branching tree symbolizing all possible outcomes of any interaction. If all possibilities exist, any paradoxes could be explained by having the paradoxical events happening in a different universe. This concept is most often used in science-fiction, but some physicists such as David Deutsch have suggested that if time travel is possible and the many-worlds interpretation is correct, then a time traveler should indeed end up in a different history than the one he started from.[1] On the other hand, Stephen Hawking has argued that even if the many-worlds interpretation is correct, we should expect each time traveler to experience a single self-consistent timeline, so that time travelers remain within their own world rather than traveling to a different one.[10]

Daniel Greenberger and Karl Svozil proposed that quantum theory gives a model for time travel without paradoxes.[44][45] In quantum theory observation causes possible states to 'collapse' into one measured state; hence, the past observed from the present is deterministic (it has only one possible state), but the present observed from the past has many possible states until our actions cause it to collapse into one state. Our actions will then be seen to have been inevitable.

Using quantum entanglement

Quantum-mechanical phenomena such as quantum teleportation, the EPR paradox, or quantum entanglement might appear to create a mechanism that allows for faster-than-light (FTL) communication or time travel, and in fact some interpretations of quantum mechanics such as the Bohm interpretation presume that some information is being exchanged between particles instantaneously in order to maintain correlations between particles.[46] This effect was referred to as "spooky action at a distance" by Einstein.

Nevertheless, the fact that causality is preserved in quantum mechanics is a rigorous result in modern quantum field theories, and therefore modern theories do not allow for time travel or FTL communication. In any specific instance where FTL has been claimed, more detailed analysis has proven that to get a signal, some form of classical communication must also be used.[citation needed] The no-communication theorem also gives a general proof that quantum entanglement cannot be used to transmit information faster than classical signals. The fact that these quantum phenomena apparently do not allow FTL time travel is often overlooked in popular press coverage of quantum teleportation experiments.[citation needed] How the rules of quantum mechanics work to preserve causality is an active area of research.[citation needed]

Philosophic understandings of time travel

The relativity of simultaneity in modern physics favors the philosophic view known as four dimensionalism in which past, present and future events all coexist in a single spacetime. Block Universe theory, or eternalism, builds on a standard method of modeling time as a dimension in physics, to give time a similar ontology to that of space. This would mean that time is just another dimension, that future events are "already there", and that there is no objective flow of time.

Presentism is a school of philosophy that holds that neither the future nor the past exist, and there are no non-present objects. In this view, time travel is impossible because there is no future or past to travel to. However, some 21st century presentists have argued that although past and future objects do not exist, there can still be definite truths about past and future events, and thus it is possible that a future truth about a time traveler deciding to appear in the present could explain the time traveler's actual existence in the present.[47][48]

Ideas from fiction

Types of time travel

Time travel themes in science fiction and the media can generally be grouped into two main types and a third, less common type (based on effect—methods are extremely varied and numerous), each of which is further subdivided. These classifications do not address the issue of time travel itself, i.e. how to travel through time, but instead call to attention differing rules of the time line.

1. The time line is consistent and can never be changed.
1.1 One does not have full control of the time travel. One example of this is The Morphail Effect. This concept of time can be referred to as circular causation. For examples of circular causation, see Robert A. Heinlein's story By His Bootstraps.
1.2 The Novikov self-consistency principle applies (named after Dr. Igor Dmitrievich Novikov, Professor of Astrophysics at Copenhagen University). The principle states that if you travel in time, you cannot act in such a way so as to create a paradox.
1.3 Any event that appears to have changed a time line has instead created a new one. It has been suggested that travel to the past would create an entire new parallel universe where the traveler would be free from paradoxes since he/she is not from that universe[49].
1.3.1 Such an event can be the life line existence of a human (or other intelligence) such that manipulation of history ends up with there being more than one of the same individual, sometimes called time clones.
1.3.2 The new time line might be a copy of the old one with changes caused by the time traveler. For example there is the Accumulative Audience Paradox where multitudes of time traveler tourists wish to attend some event in the life of Jesus or some other historical figure, where history tells us there were no such multitudes. Each tourist arrives in a reality that is a copy of the original with the added people, and no way for the tourist to travel back to the original time line.
2. The time line is flexible and is subject to change.
2.1 The time line is extremely change resistant and requires great effort to change it. Small changes will only alter the immediate future and events will conspire to maintain constant events in the far future; only large changes will alter events in the distant future. (Example: The Saga of Darren Shan, where major events in the past cannot be changed, but minor events can be affected. This is explained as if you went back in time and killed Hitler, another Nazi would take his place and commit his same actions.)
2.2 The time line is easily changed. (Example: Doctor Who, where the time line is fluid and changes often naturally; even changes to the traveler's own timeline are possible, though it is suggested such an act would destroy most of the universe.)
3. The time line is consistent, but only insofar as its consistency can be verified.
3.1 The Novikov self-consistency principle applies, but if and only if it is verified to apply. Attempts to travel into the past to change events are possible, but provided that:
-They do not interfere with the occurrence of such an attempt in the present (as would be the case in the Grandfather Paradox), and
-The change is never ultimately verified to occur by the traveler (e.g. there is no possibility of returning to the present to witness the change).

There are also numerous science fiction stories allegedly about time travel that are not internally consistent, where the traveler makes all kinds of changes to some historical time, but we do not get to see any consequences of this in our present day.[citation needed]

Immutable timelines

Time travel in a type 1 universe does not allow any paradoxes, although in 1.3, events can appear to be paradoxical.

In 1.1, time travel is constrained to prevent paradox. If one attempts to make a paradox, one undergoes involuntary or uncontrolled time travel. Michael Moorcock uses a form of this principle and calls it The Morphail Effect. In the time-travel stories of Connie Willis, time travelers encounter "slippage" which prevents them from either reaching the intended time or translates them a sufficient distance from their destination at the intended time, as to prevent any paradox from occurring.

Example: A man who travels into the past with intentions to kill Hitler finds himself on a Montana farm in late April 1945.

In 1.2, the Novikov self-consistency principle asserts that the existence of a method of time travel constrains events to remain self-consistent (i.e. no paradoxes). This will cause any attempt to violate such consistency to fail, even if extremely improbable events are required.

Example: You have a device that can send a single bit of information back to itself at a precise moment in time. You receive a bit at 10:00:00 p.m., then no bits for thirty seconds after that. If you send a bit back to 10:00:00 p.m., everything works fine. However, if you try to send a bit to 10:00:15 p.m. (a time at which no bit was received), your transmitter will mysteriously fail. Or your dog will distract you for fifteen seconds. Or your transmitter will appear to work, but as it turns out your receiver failed at exactly 10:00:15 p.m., etc. Examples of this kind of universe are found in Timemaster, a novel by Dr. Robert Forward, the Twilight Zone episode "No Time Like the Past", and the 1980 Jeannot Szwarc film Somewhere In Time (based on Richard Matheson's novel Bid Time Return).
An example which could conceivably fall into either 1.1 or 1.2 can be seen in book and film versions of Harry Potter and the Prisoner of Azkaban. Harry went back in time with Hermione to change history. As they do so it becomes apparent that they are simply performing actions that were previously seen in the story, although neither the characters nor the reader were aware of the causes of those actions at the time. This is another example of the predestination paradox. It is arguable, however, that the mechanics of time travel actually prevented any paradoxes, firstly, by preventing them from realizing a priori that time travel was occurring and secondly, by enabling them to recall the precise action to take at the precise time and keep history consistent.

In 1.3, any event that appears to have caused a paradox has instead created a new time line. The old time line remains unchanged, with the time traveler or information sent simply having vanished, never to return. A difficulty with this explanation, however, is that conservation of mass-energy would be violated for the origin timeline and the destination timeline. A possible solution to this is to have the mechanics of time travel require that mass-energy be exchanged in precise balance between past and future at the moment of travel, or to simply expand the scope of the conservation law to encompass all timelines. Some examples of this kind of time travel can be found in David Gerrold's book The Man Who Folded Himself and The Time Ships by Stephen Baxter, plus several episodes of the TV show Star Trek: The Next Generation.

Mutable timelines

Time travel in a Type 2 universe is much more complex. The biggest problem is how to explain changes in the past. One method of explanation is that once the past changes, so too do the memories of all observers. This would mean that no observer would ever observe the changing of the past (because they will not remember changing the past). This would make it hard to tell whether you are in a Type 1 universe or a Type 2 universe. You could, however, infer such information by knowing if a) communication with the past were possible or b) it appeared that the time line had never been changed as a result of an action someone remembers taking, although evidence exists that other people are changing their time lines fairly often. An example of this kind of universe is presented in Thrice Upon a Time, a novel by James P. Hogan. The Back to the Future trilogy films also seem to feature a single mutable timeline (see the Back to the Future FAQ for details on how the writers imagined time travel worked in the movies' world). By contrast, the short story Brooklyn Project by William Tenn provides a sketch of life in a Type 2 world where no one even notices as the timeline changes repeatedly.

In type 2.1, attempts are being made at changing the timeline, however, all that is accomplished in the first tries is that the way of how decisive events happen is changed; final conclusions in the bigger scheme cannot be brought to a different outcome. Example: In the Movie Deja Vu a paper note is being sent to the past with vital information to prevent the main plot incident. All that happens, though, is that an ATF agent gets killed, with the final disaster still not being prevented; also, the very same agent died in the previous version of the timeline as well, albeit under different circumstances. Finally though, the timeline is changed (Claire Kuchever is being saved from murder) by sending a human back into the past in order to prevent the murder of Claire and the main incident (a terrorist attack), which is arguably a "stronger" measure than simply sending back a paper note.

Similar to the Back to the Future movie trilogy, there seems to be a ripple effect (changes from the past 'propagate' into the present, and people in the present have altered memory of events occurred after the changes made to the timeline)
The type of timetravel in Deja Vu fits the 2.1 Type very well: Sending the paper note seems to be too "weak" a measure to cause any permanent effect, but agent Carlin going back into the past has a final decisive impact.

The science fiction writer Larry Niven suggests in his essay The Theory and Practice of Time Travel that in a type 2.1 universe, the most efficient way for the universe to "correct" a change is for time travel to never be discovered, and that in a type 2.2 universe, the very large (or infinite) number of time travelers from the endless future will cause the timeline to change wildly until it reaches a history in which time travel is never discovered. However, many other "stable" situations might also exist in which time travel occurs but no paradoxes are created; if the changeable-timeline universe finds itself in such a state no further changes will occur, and to the inhabitants of the universe it will appear identical to the type 1.2 scenario.[citation needed] This is sometimes referred to as the "Time Dilution Effect."

Few if any physicists or philosophers have taken seriously the possibility of "changing" the past except in the case of multiple universes, and in fact many have argued that this idea is logically incoherent,[50] so the mutable timeline idea is rarely considered outside of science fiction.

Also, deciding whether a given universe is of Type 2.1 or 2.2 can not be done objectively, as the categorization of timeline-invasive measures as "strong" or "weak" is arbitrary, and up to interpretation: An observer can disagree about a measure being "weak", and might, in the lack of context, argue instead that simply a mishap occurred which then led to no effective change.

An example would be the papernote sent back to the past in the film Deja Vu, as described above: Was it a too "weak" change, or was it after all just (time-local; that is, in the past) bad circumstance which made it have no effect, but it might have worked if the paper note would have been sent back 1 hour earlier, or 1 hour later into the past? As the universe in Deja Vu seems to be not entirely self-preserving from paradoxes (some, arguably minute, paradoxes, do occur), both versions seem to be equally probable, to which the film gives no further clarification.

Gradual and instantaneous

In literature, there are two methods of time travel:

1. The most commonly used method of time travel in science fiction is the instantaneous movement from one point in time to another, like using the controls on a CD player to skip to a previous or next song, though in most cases, there is a machine of some sort, and some energy expended in order to make this happen (Like the time-traveling De Lorean in Back to the Future or the phonebooth which traveled through the 'circuits of history' in Bill and Ted's Excellent Adventure). In some cases, there is not even the beginning of a scientific explanation for this kind of time travel; it's popular probably because it is more spectacular and makes time travel easier. The "Universal Remote" used by Adam Sandler in the movie Click works in the same manner, although only in one direction, the future. While his character Michael Newman can travel back to a previous point it is merely a playback which he cannot interact with.

2. In The Time Machine, H.G. Wells explains that we are moving through time with a constant speed. Time travel then is, in Wells' words, "stopping or accelerating one's drift along the time-dimension, or even turning about and traveling the other way." To expand on the audio playback analogy used above, this would be like rewinding or fast forwarding an analogue audio cassette and playing the tape at a chosen point. This method of gradual time travel is not as popular in modern science fiction. Perhaps the oldest example of this method of time travel is in Lewis Carroll's Through the Looking-Glass (1871): the White Queen is living backwards, hence her memory is working both ways. Her kind of time travel is uncontrolled: she moves through time with a constant speed of -1 and she cannot change it. T.H. White, in the first part of his Arthurian novel The Once and Future King, The Sword in the Stone (1938) used the same idea: the wizard Merlyn lives back in time, because he was born "at the wrong end of time" and has to live backwards from in front. "Some people call it having second sight", he says.

Time travel, or space-time travel?

An objection that is sometimes raised against the concept of time machines in science fiction is that they ignore the motion of the Earth between the date the time machine departs and the date it returns. The idea that a traveler can go into a machine that sends him or her to 1865 and step out into the exact same spot on Earth might be said to ignore the issue that Earth is moving through space around the Sun, which is moving in the galaxy, and so on, so that advocates of this argument imagine that "realistically" the time machine should actually reappear in space far away from the Earth's position at that date. However, according to the theory of relativity, this argument is based on a false premise. Relativity rejects the idea of absolute time and space; there can be no universal truth about the spatial distance between events which occurred at different times[51] (such as an event on Earth today and an event on Earth in 1865), and thus no objective truth about which point in space at one time is at the "same position" that the Earth was at another time. In the theory of special relativity, which deals with situations where gravity is negligible, the laws of physics work the same way in every inertial frame of reference and therefore no frame's perspective is physically better than any other frame's, and different frames disagree about whether two events at different times happened at the "same position" or "different positions". In the theory of general relativity, which incorporates the effects of gravity, all coordinate systems are on equal footing because of a feature known as "diffeomorphism invariance"[52] (also called general covariance).

Nevertheless, the idea that the Earth moves away from the time traveler when he takes a trip through time has been used in a few science fiction stories, such as the 2000 AD comic Strontium Dog, in which Johnny Alpha uses "Time Bombs" to propel an enemy several seconds into the future, during which time the movement of the Earth causes the unfortunate victim to re-materialize in space. Other science fiction stories try to anticipate this objection and offer a rationale for the fact that the traveler remains on Earth, such as the 1957 Robert Heinlein novel The Door into Summer where Heinlein essentially handwaved the issue with a single sentence: "You stay on the world line you were on." In his 1980 novel The Number of the Beast a "continua device" allows the protagonists to dial in the six (not four!) co-ordinates of space and time and it instantly moves them there—without explaining how such a device might work. The television series Seven Days also dealt with this problem; when the chrononaut would be 'rewinding', he would also be propelling himself backwards around the earth's orbit, with the intention of landing at some chosen spatial location, though seldom hitting the mark precisely.[citation needed] In Piers Anthony's Bearing an Hourglass, the potent Hourglass of the Incarnation of Time naturally moves the Incarnation in space according to the numerous movements of the globe through the solar system, the solar system through the galaxy, etc.; but by carefully negating some of the movements he can also travel in space within the limits of the planet. The television series Doctor Who cleverly avoided this issue by establishing early on in the series that the Doctor's TARDIS is able to move about in space in addition to traveling in time.

See also

Speculations

Claims of time travel

Fiction, humor

References

  1. ^ a b Deutsch, David (1991). "Quantum mechanics near closed timelike curves". Physical Review D. 44: 3197–3217. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.44.3197.
  2. ^ a b Alkon, Paul K. (1987). Origins of Futuristic Fiction. The University of Georgia Press. pp. 95–96. ISBN 0-8203-0932-X.
  3. ^ Alkon, Paul K. (1987). Origins of Futuristic Fiction. The University of Georgia Press. p. 85. ISBN 0-8203-0932-X.
  4. ^ Derleth, August (1951). Far Boundaries. Pellegrini & Cudahy. p. 3.
  5. ^ Derleth, August (1951). Far Boundaries. Pellegrini & Cudahy. pp. 11–38.
  6. ^ Flynn, John L. "Time Travel Literature". Retrieved 2006-10-28.
  7. ^ Rudwick, Martin J. S. (1992). Scenes From Deep Time. The University of Chicago Press. pp. 166–169. ISBN 0-226-73105-7.
  8. ^ Uribe, Augusto (June 1999). "The First Time Machine: Enrique Gaspar's Anacronópete". The New York Review of Science Fiction. Vol. 11, No. 10 (130): 12. {{cite journal}}: |volume= has extra text (help)
  9. ^ a b c Thorne, Kip S. (1994). Black Holes and Time Warps. W. W. Norton. pp. p. 499. ISBN 0-393-31276-3. {{cite book}}: |pages= has extra text (help) Cite error: The named reference "Thorne1" was defined multiple times with different content (see the help page).
  10. ^ a b Hawking, Steven. "Space and Time Warps" (html). Retrieved 2006-11-20.
  11. ^ NOVA Online - Sagan on Time Travel
  12. ^ http://arxiv.org/pdf/gr-qc/0204022
  13. ^ Hawking, Stephen (1992). "Chronology protection conjecture". Physical Review D. 46: 603. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.46.603.
  14. ^ Hawking, Stephen (2002). The Future of Spacetime. W. W. Norton. pp. p. 150. ISBN 0-393-02022-3. {{cite book}}: |pages= has extra text (help); Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  15. ^ a b c Gott, J. Richard (2002). "Time Travel in Einstein's Universe". {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help) p.33-130 Cite error: The named reference "Gott" was defined multiple times with different content (see the help page).
  16. ^ a b Jarrell, Mark. "The Special Theory of Relativity" (PDF). pp. 7–11. Retrieved 2006-10-27.
  17. ^ Chase, Scott I. "Tachyons entry from Usenet Physics FAQ". Retrieved 2006-10-27.
  18. ^ Visser, Matt (1996). Lorentzian Wormholes. Springer-Verlag. pp. p. 100. ISBN 1-56396-653-0. {{cite book}}: |pages= has extra text (help)
  19. ^ Thorne, Kip S. (1994). Black Holes and Time Warps. W. W. Norton. pp. p. 502. ISBN 0-393-31276-3. {{cite book}}: |pages= has extra text (help)
  20. ^ Thorne, Kip S. (1994). Black Holes and Time Warps. W. W. Norton. pp. p. 504. ISBN 0-393-31276-3. {{cite book}}: |pages= has extra text (help)
  21. ^ a b Visser, Matt (1996). Lorentzian Wormholes. Springer-Verlag. pp. p. 101. ISBN 1-56396-653-0. {{cite book}}: |pages= has extra text (help)
  22. ^ Cramer, John G. "NASA Goes FTL Part 1: Wormhole Physics". Retrieved 2006-12-02.
  23. ^ Visser, Matt (2003). "Traversable wormholes with arbitrarily small energy condition violations". Physical Review Letters. 90: 201102.1–201102.4. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.90.201102. {{cite journal}}: Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help) arXiv:gr-qc/0301003
  24. ^ Visser, Matt (1993). "From wormhole to time machine: Comments on Hawking's Chronology Protection Conjecture". Physical Review D. 47: 554–565. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.47.554. arXiv:hep-th/9202090
  25. ^ Visser, Matt (1997). "Traversable wormholes: the Roman ring". Physical Review D. 55: 5212–5214. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.55.5212. arXiv:gr-qc/9702043
  26. ^ van Stockum, Willem Jacob (1936). "The Gravitational Field of a Distribution of Particles Rotating about an Axis of Symmetry". Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh.
  27. ^ Lanczos, Kornel (1924, republished in 1997). "On a Stationary Cosmology in the Sense of Einsteins Theory of Gravitation". General Relativity and Gravitation. 29 (3). Springland Netherlands: 363–399. doi:10.1023/A:1010277120072. {{cite journal}}: Check date values in: |year= (help)
  28. ^ Earman, John (1995). Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers, and Shrieks: Singularities and Acausalities in Relativistic Spacetimes. Oxford University Press. pp. p. 21. ISBN 0-19-509591-X. {{cite book}}: |pages= has extra text (help)
  29. ^ Tipler, Frank J (1974). "Rotating Cylinders and the Possibility of Global Causality Violation". Physical Review D. 9: 2203. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.9.2203.
  30. ^ Earman, John (1995). Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers, and Shrieks: Singularities and Acausalities in Relativistic Spacetimes. Oxford University Press. pp. p. 169. ISBN 0-19-509591-X. {{cite book}}: |pages= has extra text (help)
  31. ^ Hawking, Stephen (2002). The Future of Spacetime. W. W. Norton. pp. p. 96. ISBN 0-393-02022-3. {{cite book}}: |pages= has extra text (help); Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help)
  32. ^ Hawking, Stephen (1992). "Chronology protection conjecture". Physical Review D. 46: 603–611. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.46.603.
  33. ^ Anderson, Mark (August 18–24, 2007), "Light seems to defy its own speed limit", New Scientist, vol. 195, no. 2617, p. 10{{citation}}: CS1 maint: date and year (link) CS1 maint: date format (link)
  34. ^ Franklin, Ben A. (March 11, 1982), "The night the planets were aligned with Baltimore lunacy", New York Times.
  35. ^ Goodman, Linda (1978). Linda Goodman's Love Signs, Leo-Aquarius chap. Harper and Row. ISBN 978-0060968960.
  36. ^ MacAdams, Lewis (January, 1982), Wet Magazine.
  37. ^ The Crater Baltimore Project
  38. ^ [gr-qc/0102010] Many worlds in one
  39. ^ Taking the Cosmic Shortcut - ABC Science Online
  40. ^ Transcript of interview with Dr. Marc Rayman at "Space Place"
  41. ^ "http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/time/thinktime.html". {{cite journal}}: Cite has empty unknown parameter: |1= (help); Cite journal requires |journal= (help); External link in |title= (help)
  42. ^ Physics for Scientists and Engineers with Modern Physics, Fifth Edition, p.1258.
  43. ^ Vaidman, Lev. "Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics". Retrieved 2006-10-28.
  44. ^ Greenberger, Daniel M (2005). "Quantum Theory Looks at Time Travel". {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help); Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help) arXiv:quant-ph/0506027
  45. ^ BBC News - New model 'permits time travel'
  46. ^ Goldstein, Sheldon. "Bohmian Mechanics". Retrieved 2006-10-30.
  47. ^ Keller, Simon (2001). "Presentists should believe in time-travel" (PDF). Australian Journal of Philosophy. 79.3: 333–345. doi:10.1080/713931204. {{cite journal}}: Unknown parameter |coauthors= ignored (|author= suggested) (help); Unknown parameter |month= ignored (help)
  48. ^ This view is contested by another contemporary advocate of presentism, Craig Bourne, in his recent book A Future for Presentism, although for substantially different (and more complex) reasons.
  49. ^ "Time Travel and Resolving Paradoxes in Fiction"
  50. ^ see this discussion between two philosophers, for example
  51. ^ Geroch, Robert (1978). General Relativity From A to B. The University of Chicago Press. p. 124.
  52. ^ Einstein Online: Actors on a changing stage

Further reading

  • Davies, Paul (1996). About Time. Pocket Books. ISBN 0-684-81822-1.
  • Davies, Paul (2002). How to Build a Time Machine. Penguin Books Ltd. ISBN 0-14-100534-3.
  • Gale, Richard M (1968). The Philosophy of Time. Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 0-333-00042-0.
  • Gott, J. Richard. Time Travel in Einstein's Universe: The Physical Possibilities of Travel Through Time. ISBN 0-618-25735-7.
  • Gribbin, John (1985). In Search of Schrödinger's Cat. Corgi Adult. ISBN 0-552-12555-5.
  • Miller, Kristie (2005). "Time travel and the open future". Disputatio. 1 (19): 223–232.
  • Nahin, Paul J. (2001). Time Machines: Time Travel in Physics, Metaphysics, and Science Fiction. Springer-Verlag New York Inc. ISBN 0-387-98571-9.
  • Nahin, Paul J. (1997). Time Travel: A writer's guide to the real science of plausible time travel. Writer's Digest Books. Cincinnati, Ohio. ISBN 0-89879-748-9
  • Nikolic, H. "Causal paradoxes: a conflict between relativity and the arrow of time". {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help) arXiv:gr-qc/0403121
  • Pagels, Heinz (1985). Perfect Symmetry, the Search for the Beginning of Time. Simon & Schuster. ISBN 0-671-46548-1.
  • Pickover, Clifford (1999). Time: A Traveler's Guide. Oxford University Press Inc, USA. ISBN 0-19-513096-0.
  • Randles, Jenny (2005). Breaking the Time Barrier. Simon & Schuster Ltd. ISBN 0-7434-9259-5.
  • Shore, Graham M. "Constructing Time Machines". Int. J. Mod. Phys. A, Theoretical. arXiv:gr-qc/0210048
  • Toomey, David (2007). The New Time Travelers: A Journey to the Frontiers of Physics. W.W. Norton & Company. ISBN 978-0-393-06013-3.

External links

Template:Link FA