axiom

from Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

An axiom (from the Greek ἀξίωμα axíoma , "appreciation, judgment, principle accepted as true") is a principle of a theory , a science or an axiomatic system that is not justified or deductively derived within this system .

Delimitations

Within a theory that can be formalized, a thesis is a proposition that is to be proven. An axiom is a proposition that is not supposed to be proved in theory, but is presupposed without proof. If the chosen axioms of the theory are logically independent , none of them can be derived from the others. The axioms of this calculus can always be derived within the framework of a formal calculus . In the formal or syntactic sense, this is a proof ; From a semantic point of view, it is a circular argument . Otherwise the following applies: "If a derivation is based on the axioms of a calculus or on true statements, one speaks of a proof."

Axiom is used as the opposite of theorem (in the narrower sense). Theorems like axioms are theorems of a formalized calculus that are connected by derivative relationships. Theorems are theorems that are derived from axioms through formal proofs. Sometimes, however, the terms thesis and theorem are used in a broader sense for all valid propositions of a formal system; H. as a generic term that includes both axioms and theorems in the original sense.

Axioms can thus be understood as conditions of the complete theory insofar as they can be expressed in a formalized calculus. Within an interpreted formal language , different theories can be distinguished by the choice of axioms. In the case of uninterpreted calculi of formal logic , instead of theories, one speaks of logical systems that are completely determined by axioms and rules of inference . This relativizes the concept of deducibility or provability: It only ever exists in relation to a given system. The axioms and the derived statements belong to the object language , the rules to the metalanguage .

However, a calculus is not necessarily an axiomatic calculus, which therefore consists of “a set of axioms and the smallest possible set of inference rules”. There are also proof calculi and tableau calculi .

Immanuel Kant calls axioms “synthetic principles a priori, provided they are immediately certain” and by this definition excludes them from the field of philosophy. This is based on concepts which, as abstract images, never have any evidence as an object of immediate intuition. He therefore distinguishes the discursive principles of philosophy from the intuitive principles of mathematics: the former would have to "be comfortable with justifying their authority on account of them by thorough deduction" and therefore do not meet the criteria of an a priori.

Distinctions

The term axiom has three basic meanings. He describes

  1. an immediately illuminating principle - the classic (material) axiom concept,
  2. a natural law that can be postulated as a principle for empirically well-confirmed rules - the scientific (physical) axiom concept,
  3. a starting sentence that is assumed to be valid in a calculus of a formal language - the modern (formal) concept of axioms .

Classic axiom term

The classical axiom is traced back to the elements of the geometry of Euclid and the Analytica posteriora of Aristotle . In this conception, axiom denotes an immediately illuminating principle or a reference to such a principle. An axiom in this essentialist sense does not need any proof because of its empirical evidence. Axioms were seen as absolutely true propositions about existing objects that oppose these propositions as objective realities. This importance was predominant until the 19th century.

At the end of the 19th century there was a “cutting of the cord from reality”. The systematic investigation of different axiom systems for different geometries ( Euclidean , hyperbolic , spherical geometry, etc.), which could not possibly all describe the actual world, had to result in the axiom concept being understood more formalistically and axioms as a whole taking on a conventional character in the sense of definitions . As pioneering the writings proved David Hilbert to axiomatic that the product derived from the empirical sciences postulate evidence of the formal criteria of completeness and consistency replaced. An alternative way of understanding an axiom system does not simply refer to the actual world, but follows the scheme: If any structure fulfills the axioms, then it also fulfills the derivations from the axioms (so-called theorems ). Such views can be located in implicationism, deductivism or eliminative structuralism.

In axiomatized calculi in the sense of modern formal logic, the classic epistemological (evidence, certainty), ontological (reference to ontologically more fundamental things) or conventional (acceptance in a certain context) criteria for marking axioms can be omitted. Axioms only differ formally from theorems in that they are the basis of logical deductions in a given calculus. As a "fundamental" and " independent " principle, they cannot be derived from other starting sentences within the axiom system and are therefore not accessible to any proof.

Scientific axiom concept

In the empirical sciences, axioms also refer to fundamental laws that have been empirically confirmed many times. Newton's axioms of mechanics are given as an example .

Scientific theories, especially physics, are also based on axioms. From these theories are inferred, the theorems and corollaries of which make predictions about the outcome of experiments . If statements of the theory contradict experimental observation, the axioms are adjusted. For example, Newton's axioms only provide good predictions for “slow” and “large” systems and have been replaced or supplemented by the axioms of special relativity and quantum mechanics . Nevertheless, one continues to use Newton's axioms for such systems, since the conclusions are simpler and the results are sufficiently precise for most applications.

Formal axiom concept

By Hilbert a formal axiom term was dominant (1899): An axiom is any unabgeleitete statement. This is a purely formal quality. The evidence or the ontological status of an axiom is irrelevant and is left to a separate interpretation .

An axiom is then a fundamental proposition that

  • Is part of a formalized system of sentences,
  • is accepted without evidence and
  • from which, together with other axioms, all propositions (theorems) of the system are logically derived.

It is sometimes claimed that axioms are completely arbitrary in this understanding: An axiom is "an unproven and therefore not understood sentence", because whether an axiom is based on insight and is therefore "understandable" initially does not matter. It is true that an axiom - related to a theory - is unproven. But that does not mean that an axiom has to be unprovable. The quality of being an axiom is relative to a formal system. What is an axiom in one science may be a theorem in another.

An axiom is misunderstood only insofar as its truth is not formally proven, but presupposed. The modern concept of axioms serves to decouple the axiom property from the problem of evidence, but this does not necessarily mean that there is no evidence. It is, however, a defining feature of the axiomatic method that in the deduction of the theorems, conclusions are only drawn on the basis of formal rules and no use is made of the interpretation of the axiomatic signs.

Examples of axioms

Traditional logic

Classic logic

The original formulation comes from the naive set theory of Georg Cantor and only seemed to clearly express the connection between extension and intention of a term . It was a great shock when it turned out that in the axiomatization by Gottlob Frege it could not be added without contradiction to the other axioms, but gave rise to Russell's antinomy .

mathematics

Axioms are the foundation of mathematics.

In general, terms such as natural numbers , monoid , group , ring , body , Hilbert space , topological space, etc. are characterized in mathematics by a system of axioms. One speaks, for example, of the Peano axioms (for natural numbers), the group axioms , the ring axioms , etc. Sometimes individual requirements (including the conclusions) are also called law in a system (e.g. the associative law ).

A special axiom system of the examples mentioned - the natural numbers with the Peano axioms possibly excluded (see below) - is to be understood as a definition . In order to be able to address a certain mathematical object, e.g. as a monoid (and then infer further properties), it has to be proven (with the help of other axioms or theorems) that the requirements formulated in the axiom system of the monoid all apply to the object. An important example is the sequential execution of functions, for which the proof of associativity is not completely trivial. If this proof is insufficient for one of the axioms, then the object in question could not be regarded as a monoid. (The proof of the associativity of the Fibonacci multiplication, which goes back to D. Knuth , is extremely difficult .)

In this respect, many of the “axiom systems” mentioned are not at all (and are in direct contrast to) fundamental statements that are “ accepted without evidence” as “in-derived statements” .

  • The field axioms in connection with the arrangement axioms and the completeness axiom define the real numbers .
  • Axiom of parallels : “For every straight line and every point that is not on this straight line, there is exactly one straight line through this point parallel to the straight line.” This postulate of Euclidean geometry was always considered less plausible than the others. Since its validity was contested, attempts were made to derive it from the other definitions and postulates. During the axiomatization of geometry around the turn of the 19th century, it turned out that such a derivation is not possible, since it is logically independent of the axiomatization of the other postulates . This cleared the way for the recognition of non-Euclidean geometries .
  • The term “probability” has been defined exactly implicitly since 1933 by a system of axioms set up by Kolmogorow . This was the first time that all the different stochastic schools - French, German, British, frequentists, Bayesians, probabilists and statisticians - were provided with a uniform theory.

Although there are other basic systems ( theories of the first order ), the Peano axioms are mostly used as a basis for counting in natural numbers without further reference. For example:

physics

Proposals for the axiomatization of important sub-areas

Theories of empirical science can also be reconstructed “axiomatically” . In the philosophy of science , however, there are different understandings of what it actually means to “axiomatise a theory”. Axiomatizations have been proposed for different physical theories. Hans Reichenbach devoted himself a. a. in three monographs his proposal for an axiomatic of the theory of relativity , where he was particularly strongly influenced by Hilbert. Even Alfred Robb and Constantin Carathéodory laid Axiomatisierungsvorschläge the special theory of relativity before. For both the special and the general theory of relativity there are now a large number of attempts at axiomatization discussed in the philosophy of science and in the philosophy of physics . Patrick Suppes and others have proposed a much-discussed axiomatic reconstruction in the modern sense for classical particle mechanics in their Newtonian formulation, and Georg Hamel , a student of Hilbert, and Hans Hermes have already presented axiomatizations of classical mechanics. The company of Günther Ludwig is still one of the most popular proposals for axiomatizing quantum mechanics . For the axiomatic quantum field theory v. a. Arthur Wightman's formulation from the 1950s is important. In the field of cosmology , axiomatization and the like a. Edward Arthur Milne was particularly influential. For classical thermodynamics there are axiomatization proposals u. a. by Giles, Boyling, Jauch, Lieb and Yngvason. For all physical theories that operate with probabilities, especially statistical mechanics , the axiomatization of probability calculation by Kolmogorow became important.

Relationship between experiment and theory

The axioms of a physical theory can neither be formally proven nor, according to the view that has become commonplace, directly and collectively verified or falsifiable through observations . According to a view of theories and their relationship to experiments and the resulting idiom, which is particularly widespread in epistemological structuralism , tests of a certain theory in reality usually concern statements of the form “this system is a classical particle mechanics”. If a corresponding theory test is successful, z. If, for example, correct predictions of measured values ​​are given, this check can serve as confirmation that a corresponding system was correctly counted among the intended applications of the corresponding theory, and in the event of repeated failures, the number of intended applications can and should be reduced by corresponding types of systems become.

literature

Articles in subject-specific encyclopedias and dictionaries

Monographs

  • Evandro Agazzi : Introduzione ai problemi dell'assiomatica. Milan 1961.
  • Robert Blanché : Axiomatics. Routledge, London 1962.
  • Euclid : The elements. Harri Deutsch, Frankfurt am Main, 4th ext. Edition. 2005.
  • David Hilbert et al. a .: Basics of geometry. Teubner 2002, ISBN 3-519-00237-X .
  • Árpád Szabó : Beginnings of Greek Mathematics. Oldenbourg 1969, ISBN 3-486-47201-1 .
  • Bochenski: The contemporary thought methods. 10th edition. 1993, p. 73 ff.
  • Carnap: Introduction to Symbolic Logic. 3. Edition. 1968, p. 172 ff.
  • Hilbert / Ackermann: Basic features of theoretical logic. 6th edition. 1972, p. 24.
  • Kutschera: Frege. 1989, p. 154 f.
  • Hermann Schüling: The history of the axiomatic method in the 16th and early 17th centuries. Change in the understanding of science . [Studies and materials on the history of philosophy; 13]. Georg Olms, Hildesheim 1969.
  • Nagel, Newmann: Gödel's proof. In: Meixner (Hrsg.): Philosophy of logic. 2003, p. 150 (169).
  • Tarski: Introduction to Mathematical Logic. 5th edition. 1977, p. 126 ff.

Web links

Wiktionary: Axiom  - explanations of meanings, word origins, synonyms, translations

Individual evidence

  1. Duden | Axiom | Spelling, meaning, definition, origin. Retrieved November 22, 2019 .
  2. ^ Peter Prechtl: Axiom . In: Helmut Glück (Hrsg.): Metzler Lexikon Sprache . JB Metzler Verlag GmbH, Stuttgart 2016, ISBN 978-3-476-02641-5 , p. 81 .
  3. thesis . In: Regenbogen, Meyer: Dictionary of Philosophical Terms. 2005.
  4. derivation . In: Regenbogen, Meyer: Dictionary of Philosophical Terms. 2005.
  5. So in Tarski: Introduction to mathematical logic. 5th edition. (1977), p. 127.
  6. Cf. Carnap: Introduction to Symbolic Logic. 3. Edition. (1968), p. 172.
  7. So z. B. Paul Ruppen: Introduction to formal logic. A learning and exercise book for non-mathematicians. Peter Lang, Bern 1996, p. 125.
  8. a b Bochenski: The contemporary methods of thinking. 10th ed. (1993), p. 79.
  9. ^ Bußmann: Lexicon of Linguistics. 3rd edition, 2002, calculus.
  10. Immanuel Kant: Critique of Pure Reason . In: Benno Erdmann (Hrsg.): Edition of the Prussian Academy of Sciences . tape III . Georg Reimer, Berlin 1904, p. 480 f .
  11. Ulrich Felgner: Hilbert's "Fundamentals of Geometry" and their position in the history of the fundamental discussion . In: Annual report of the German Mathematicians Association . tape 115 , no. 3 , 2014, p. 185-206 , doi : 10.1365 / s13291-013-0071-5 .
  12. See e.g. B. Michael Potter: Set Theory and its Philosophy. A Critical Introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford / New York 2004, p. 8.
  13. See Joseph Maria Bocheński : The contemporary methods of thinking. 10th edition 1993, p. 78 f.
  14. ^ Rainbow / Meyer: Dictionary of Philosophical Terms (2005) / Axiom.
  15. ^ A b Seiffert: Theory of Science IV. 1997, beginning.
  16. ^ Seiffert: Wissenschaftstheorie IV. 1997, Axiom.
  17. ^ Carnap: Introduction to Symbolic Logic. 3rd ed., 1968, p. 174.
  18. ^ Spree, in: Rehfus: Short dictionary philosophy. 2003, axiom.
  19. Cf. introductory and representative of the state of the debate at the time, Wolfgang Stegmüller : Problems and Results of the Philosophy of Science and Analytical Philosophy, Volume II: Theory and Experience, Second Partial Volume: Theory Structures and Theory Dynamics. Springer, Berlin a. a., 2nd ed., 1985, p. 34 ff.
  20. Cf. especially H. Reichenbach: Axiomatics of the relativistic space-time theory. Vieweg, Braunschweig 1924.
  21. On the contemporary discussion points, see K. Brading, T. Ryckman: Hilbert's 'Foundations of Physics': Gravitation and Electromagnetism within the axiomatic method. In: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39. 2008, 102–53.
  22. See AA Rob: A Theory of Space and Time. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1914.
  23. Cf. C. Carathéodory: On the axiomatics of the theory of relativity. In: Meeting reports of the Prussian Academy of Sciences. Physical-mathematical class 5. 1924, 12–27.
  24. See JCC McKinsey, AC Sugar, P. Suppes: Axiomatic Foundations of Classical Particle Mechanics. In: Journal of Rational Mechanics and Analysis 2. 1953, pp. 253-272. This approach is recapitulated in a somewhat modified form and discussed in Stegmüller, l. c., p. 106 ff.
  25. Cf. G. Hamel: Die Axioms der Mechanik. In: H. Geiger, K. Scheel (Hrsg.): Handbuch der Physik, Vol. 5: Mechanics of points and rigid bodies. Springer, Berlin 1927, pp. 1-42.
  26. H. Hermes: An axiomatization of general mechanics. Research on logic, New Series 3, Hirzel, Leipzig 1938. Ders .: On the axiomatization of mechanics. In: L. Henkin, P. Suppes, A. Tarski (Eds.): The Axiomatic Method. Amsterdam 1959, pp. 282–290 ( digitized at archive.org ).
  27. Cf. G. Ludwig: Interpretation of the term "physical theory" and axiomatic foundation of the Hilbert space structure of quantum mechanics through the main principles of measurement. Lecture Notes in Physics 4, Springer, Berlin 1970 and Ders .: An Axiomatic Basis for Quantum Mechanics. Vol. 1/2, Springer, Berlin 1985/1987.
  28. Published in 1964 in A. Wightman, Ray Streater : PCT, Spin, Statistics and all that. BI University Pocket Book 1964 ( PCT, Spin, Statistics and all that. Benjamin, New York 1964.)
  29. See the introductory overview in George Gale:  Cosmology: Methodological Debates in the 1930s and 1940s. In: Edward N. Zalta (Ed.): Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  30. See R. Giles: Mathematical foundations of thermodynamics. Pergamon, Oxford 1964.
  31. See JB Boyling: An axiomatic approach to classical thermodynamics. In: Proceedings of the Royal Society of London 329. 1972, 35-71.
  32. See J. Jauch: On a new foundation of equilibrium thermodynamics. In: Foundations of Physics 2. (1972), 327-332.
  33. See EH Lieb, J. Yngvason: The physics and mathematics of the second law of thermodynamics . In: Physics Reports 310.1999, 1-96.314.669, arxiv : cond-mat / 9708200 .
  34. Cf. NA Kolmogorov: Basic Concepts of Probability. Springer, Berlin 1933. Introduction to current philosophical interpretations of probabilities and Kolmogorov's foundations: Alan Hájek:  Interpretations of Probability. In: Edward N. Zalta (Ed.): Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . ; Thomas Hochkirchen: The axiomatization of probability theory and its contexts. From Hilbert's Sixth Problem to Kolmogoroff's Basic Concepts. Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, Göttingen 1999.