Jürgen Habermas: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m →‎top: Fixed typo
Tags: Mobile edit Mobile app edit Android app edit
(48 intermediate revisions by 36 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|German social theorist and philosopher (born 1929)}}
{{Short description|German social theorist and philosopher (born 1929)}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=September 2020}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=December 2023}}
{{Infobox philosopher
{{Infobox philosopher
| name = Jürgen Habermas
| name = Jürgen Habermas
| image = Habermas10 (14298469242).jpg
| image = Habermas10 (14298469242).jpg
| caption = Habermas in 2014
| caption = Habermas in 2014
| birth_name = Jürgen Habermas
| birth_date = {{Birth date and age|df=y|1929|6|18}}
| birth_date = {{Birth date and age|df=y|1929|6|18}}
| birth_place = [[Düsseldorf]], [[Rhine Province]], [[Free State of Prussia|Prussia]], [[Weimar Republic|Germany]]
| birth_place = [[Düsseldorf]], [[Rhine Province]], [[Free State of Prussia|Prussia]], [[Weimar Republic|Germany]]
Line 11: Line 12:
| region = [[Western philosophy]]
| region = [[Western philosophy]]
| era = [[Contemporary philosophy]]
| era = [[Contemporary philosophy]]
| school_tradition = {{hlist| [[Continental philosophy]] | [[Critical theory]] | [[Neopragmatism]]<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.iep.utm.edu/pragmati/ |title=Pragmatism |website=iep.utm.edu|publisher=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> }}
| school_tradition = {{hlist| [[Continental philosophy]] | [[Critical theory]] | [[Neopragmatism]]<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.iep.utm.edu/pragmati/ |title=Pragmatism |website=iep.utm.edu |publisher=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}</ref> }}
| education = [[University of Bonn]] ([[PhD]])<br />[[University of Marburg]] ([[Dr. phil. hab.]])
| education = [[University of Bonn]] ([[PhD]])<br />[[University of Marburg]] ([[Dr. phil. hab.]])
| main_interests = {{hlist| [[Epistemology]] | [[Social theory]] | [[Political theory]] | [[Philosophy of law]] | [[Rationalization (sociology)|Rationalization]] | [[Pragmatics]] | [[Pragmatism]] }}
| main_interests = {{hlist| [[Epistemology]] | [[Social theory]] | [[Political theory]] | [[Philosophy of law]] | [[Rationalization (sociology)|Rationalization]] | [[Pragmatics]] | [[Pragmatism]] }}
Line 26: Line 27:
* [[Ideal speech situation]]
* [[Ideal speech situation]]
* [[Instrumental and value-rational action]]
* [[Instrumental and value-rational action]]
* Monological-dialogical ethics distinction<ref>Anders Bordum, "Immanuel Kant, Jürgen Habermas and the categorical imperative", ''Philosophy & Social Criticism'' '''31'''(7), 2005.</ref>
* Monological-dialogical ethics distinction<ref>{{cite journal |first=Anders |last=Bordum |title=Immanuel Kant, Jürgen Habermas and the categorical imperative |journal=[[Philosophy & Social Criticism]] |volume=31 |number=7 |date=2005}}</ref>
* [[Performative contradiction]]
* [[Performative contradiction]]
* [[Postsecularism]]
* [[Postsecularism]]
Line 35: Line 36:
* [[Universal pragmatics]]
* [[Universal pragmatics]]
{{endplainlist}}
{{endplainlist}}
| signature = Jürgen Habermas signature.jpg
| signature = Habermas signature.svg
| influences = {{hlist| [[Max Weber|Weber]] | [[Émile Durkheim|Durkheim]] | [[George Herbert Mead|Mead]] | [[Sigmund Freud|Freud]] | [[Karl Marx|Marx]] | [[Wilhelm Dilthey|Dilthey]] | [[Talcott Parsons|Parsons]] | [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] |[[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling|Schelling]] | [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]] | [[Søren Kierkegaard|Kierkegaard]] | [[Karl-Otto Apel|Apel]] | [[Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] | [[Jean Piaget|Piaget]] | [[Max Horkheimer|Horkheimer]] | [[Theodor W. Adorno|Adorno]] | [[Herbert Marcuse|Marcuse]] | [[Ludwig Wittgenstein|Wittgenstein]] | [[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce]] | [[J. L. Austin|Austin]] | [[Wolfgang Abendroth|Abendroth]] | [[John Dewey|Dewey]] | [[John Rawls|Rawls]] |[[Richard Rorty|Rorty]]|[[Karl Bühler|Bühler]]<ref>Christian Damböck (ed.), ''Influences on the Aufbau'', Springer, 2015, p. 258.</ref> }}
| influenced = {{hlist| [[Claus Offe|Offe]] | [[Axel Honneth|Honneth]] | [[Rainer Forst|Forst]] | [[Carol C. Gould|Gould]] | [[Thomas A. McCarthy|McCarthy]] | [[Hans-Hermann Hoppe|Hoppe]] | [[Seyla Benhabib|Benhabib]] | [[Nancy Fraser|Fraser]] | [[Michael Friedman (philosopher)|Friedman]] | [[Nikolas Kompridis|Kompridis]] | [[Ken Wilber|Wilber]] | [[Cristina Lafont|Lafont]]}}
| spouse = {{marriage|Ute Wesselhöft|1955}}
| spouse = {{marriage|Ute Wesselhöft|1955}}


| children = {{hlist|Tilmann (b. 1956)|[[Rebekka Habermas|Rebekka]] (b. 1959)|Judith (b. 1967)}}
| children = {{hlist|Tilmann (b. 1956)|[[Rebekka Habermas|Rebekka]] (1959–2023)|Judith (b. 1967)}}
}}
}}


'''Jürgen Habermas''' ({{IPAc-en|UK|ˈ|h|ɑː|b|ər|m|æ|s}}, {{IPAc-en|US|-|m|ɑː|s}};<ref>[https://www.collinsdictionary.com/dictionary/english/habermas "Habermas"]. ''[[Collins English Dictionary]]''.</ref> {{IPA-de|ˈjʏʁɡn̩ ˈhaːbɐmaːs|lang|De-Jürgen Habermas.ogg}};<ref>Max Mangold and Dudenredaktion: ''Duden Aussprachewörterbuch.'' In: ''Der Duden in zwölf Bänden.'' Volume 6, 6th edition, Dudenverlag, Mannheim/Leipzig/Wien/Zürich 2005 {{ISBN|978-3-411-04066-7}}, "Jürgen" p. 446 and "Habermas" p. 383.</ref><ref>{{cite book|last1=Krech|first1=Eva-Maria|last2=Stock|first2=Eberhard|last3=Hirschfeld|first3=Ursula|last4=Anders|first4=Lutz Christian|title=Deutsches Aussprachewörterbuch|url=https://archive.org/details/deutschesausspra00krec|url-access=limited|trans-title=German Pronunciation Dictionary|language=de|year=2009|publisher=Walter de Gruyter|location=Berlin|isbn=978-3-11-018202-6|pages=[https://archive.org/details/deutschesausspra00krec/page/n572 561], 629}}</ref> born 18 June 1929) is a German philosopher and [[social theorist]] in the tradition of [[critical theory]] and [[pragmatism]]. His work addresses [[communicative rationality]] and the [[public sphere]].
'''Jürgen Habermas''' ({{IPAc-en|UK|ˈ|h|ɑː|b|ər|m|æ|s}}, {{IPAc-en|US|-|m|ɑː|s}};<ref>[https://www.collinsdictionary.com/dictionary/english/habermas "Habermas"]. ''[[Collins English Dictionary]]''.</ref> {{IPA-de|ˈjʏʁɡn̩ ˈhaːbɐmaːs|lang|De-Jürgen Habermas.ogg}};<ref>Max Mangold and Dudenredaktion: ''Duden Aussprachewörterbuch.'' In: ''Der Duden in zwölf Bänden.'' Volume 6, 6th edition, Dudenverlag, Mannheim/Leipzig/Wien/Zürich 2005 {{ISBN|978-3-411-04066-7}}, "Jürgen" p. 446 and "Habermas" p. 383.</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Krech |first1=Eva-Maria |last2=Stock |first2=Eberhard |last3=Hirschfeld |first3=Ursula |last4=Anders |first4=Lutz Christian |title=Deutsches Aussprachewörterbuch |url=https://archive.org/details/deutschesausspra00krec |url-access=limited |trans-title=German Pronunciation Dictionary |language=de |year=2009 |publisher=[[Walter de Gruyter]] |location=Berlin |isbn=978-3-11-018202-6 |pages=[https://archive.org/details/deutschesausspra00krec/page/n572 561], 629}}</ref> born 18 June 1929) is a German philosopher and [[social theorist]] in the tradition of [[critical theory]] and [[pragmatism]]. His work addresses [[communicative rationality]] and the [[public sphere]].


Associated with the [[Frankfurt School]], Habermas's work focuses on the foundations of [[epistemology]] and [[social theory]], the analysis of [[advanced capitalism]] and [[democracy]], the [[rule of law]] in a critical [[Sociocultural evolution|social-evolutionary context]], albeit within the confines of the [[natural law]] tradition,<ref>Cf. Thomas Kupka, [https://www.jstor.org/stable/23999017?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents Jürgen Habermas' diskurstheoretische Reformulierung des klassischen Vernunftrechts], ''Kritische Justiz'' 27 (1994), pp. 461–469. The continuity with the natural law tradition was controversial at the time, see the reply by Habermas's PhD-student [[:de:Klaus Günther (Jurist)|Klaus Günther]], Diskurstheorie des Rechts oder liberales Naturrecht in diskurstheoretischem Gewande?, ''[https://www.jstor.org/stable/23999018?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents Kritische Justiz]'' 27 (1994), pp. 470–487.</ref> and contemporary politics, particularly [[German politics]]. Habermas's theoretical system is devoted to revealing the possibility of [[reason]], [[Political emancipation|emancipation]], and rational-critical communication latent in modern institutions and in the human capacity to deliberate and pursue rational interests. Habermas is known for his work on the concept of [[modernity]], particularly with respect to the discussions of [[Rationalization (sociology)|rationalization]] originally set forth by [[Max Weber]]. He has been influenced by [[American pragmatism]], [[Action theory (sociology)|action theory]], and [[poststructuralism]].
Associated with the [[Frankfurt School]], Habermas's work focuses on the foundations of [[epistemology]] and [[social theory]], the analysis of [[advanced capitalism]] and [[democracy]], the [[rule of law]] in a critical [[Sociocultural evolution|social-evolutionary context]], albeit within the confines of the [[natural law]] tradition,<ref>Cf. Thomas Kupka, [https://www.jstor.org/stable/23999017?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents Jürgen Habermas' diskurstheoretische Reformulierung des klassischen Vernunftrechts], ''Kritische Justiz'' 27 (1994), pp. 461–469. The continuity with the natural law tradition was controversial at the time, see the reply by Habermas's PhD-student [[:de:Klaus Günther (Jurist)|Klaus Günther]], Diskurstheorie des Rechts oder liberales Naturrecht in diskurstheoretischem Gewande?, ''[https://www.jstor.org/stable/23999018?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents Kritische Justiz]'' 27 (1994), pp. 470–487.</ref> and contemporary politics, particularly [[German politics]]. Habermas's theoretical system is devoted to revealing the possibility of [[reason]], [[Political emancipation|emancipation]], and rational-critical communication latent in modern institutions and in the human capacity to deliberate and pursue rational interests. Habermas is known for his work on the concept of [[modernity]], particularly with respect to the discussions of [[Rationalization (sociology)|rationalization]] originally set forth by [[Max Weber]]. He has been influenced by [[American pragmatism]], [[Action theory (sociology)|action theory]], and [[poststructuralism]].

Although an atheist, Habermas has recently spoke of the need for the West to continue its continuity with traditional Christian ethics stating “religion seems to have the ability to motivate individuals to do good in a manner that secularism cannot.” When he received the Holberg Price Award in Norway in 2005, he addressed the need for a renewed respect for traditional Christian morality.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Herland |first=Hanne Nabintu |date=December 22, 2020 |title=Famous atheist fights for Christian ethics, Jürgen Habermas – Nabintu, WND |url=https://hannenabintuherland.com/religion/famous-atheist-fights-for-christianity-god-delusion-ethics-jurgen-habermas-hanne-nabintu-herland-wnd/ |url-status=live}}</ref>


==Biography==
==Biography==
{{Frankfurt School}}
{{Frankfurt School}}


Habermas was born in [[Düsseldorf]], [[Rhine Province]], in 1929. He was born with a [[Cleft lip and cleft palate|cleft palate]] and had corrective surgery twice during childhood.<ref>{{cite ssrn |title=Disabling Democracy: How Disability Reconfigures Deliberative Democratic Norms|first1=Clifford|last1=Simplican|last2=Stacy|date=28 October 2017|ssrn = 1451092}}</ref> Habermas argues that his speech disability made him think differently about the importance of deep dependence and of communication.<ref>Habermas, Jurgen. 2008. Between Naturalism and Religion: Philosophical Essays. (First chapter).</ref> He grew up in [[Gummersbach]].
Habermas was born in [[Düsseldorf]], [[Rhine Province]], in 1929.<ref>{{Cite web |title=The philosopher who rejected a €225,000 prize from the UAE – DW – 05/03/2021 |url=https://www.dw.com/en/j%C3%BCrgen-habermas-who-is-the-philosopher-who-rejected-a-prize-from-the-uae/a-49234310 |access-date=2024-03-28 |website=dw.com |language=en}}</ref> He was born with a [[Cleft lip and cleft palate|cleft palate]] and had corrective surgery twice during childhood.<ref>{{cite SSRN |title=Disabling Democracy: How Disability Reconfigures Deliberative Democratic Norms |first1=Clifford |last1=Simplican |last2=Stacy |date=28 October 2017 |ssrn=1451092}}</ref> Habermas argues that his speech disability made him think differently about the importance of deep dependence and of communication.<ref>{{cite book |last=Habermas |first=Jürgen |date=2008 |title=Between Naturalism and Religion: Philosophical Essays |chapter=First}}</ref> He grew up in [[Gummersbach]].


As a young teenager, he was profoundly affected by [[World War II]]. Until his graduation from [[grammar school]], Habermas lived in [[Gummersbach]], near [[Cologne]]. His father, Ernst Habermas, was executive director of the Cologne Chamber of Industry and Commerce, and was described by Habermas as a Nazi sympathizer and, from 1933, a member of the [[Nazi Party|NSDAP]]. Habermas himself was a ''Jungvolkführer'', a leader of the [[Deutsches Jungvolk|German Jungvolk]], which was a section of the [[Hitler Youth]]. He was brought up in a staunchly [[Protestant]] [[milieu]], his grandfather being the director of the seminary in Gummersbach. He studied at the universities of [[University of Göttingen|Göttingen]] (1949/50), [[University of Zurich|Zurich]] (1950/51), and [[University of Bonn|Bonn]] (1951–54) and earned a doctorate in [[philosophy]] from Bonn in 1954 with a dissertation written on the conflict between "the Absolute" and [[history]] in [[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling|Schelling]]'s thought, entitled, ''{{lang|de|Das Absolute und die Geschichte. Von der Zwiespältigkeit in Schellings Denken}}'' ("The Absolute and History: On the Schism in Schelling's Thought").<ref name="Habermas p. ">{{cite journal | last=Habermas | first=Jürgen | title=Das Absolute und die Geschichte | journal=University Library Heidelberg | year=1954 | doi=10.11588/DIGLIT.41402 | url=https://digi.ub.uni-heidelberg.de/diglit/habermas1954 | language=de | access-date=3 December 2022 | page=}}</ref> His dissertation committee included [[Erich Rothacker]] and [[Oskar Becker]].<ref name="Habermas p. " />
As a young teenager, he was profoundly affected by [[World War II]]. Until his graduation from [[grammar school]], Habermas lived in [[Gummersbach]], near [[Cologne]]. His father, Ernst Habermas, was executive director of the Cologne Chamber of Industry and Commerce, and was described by Habermas as a Nazi sympathizer and, from 1933, a member of the Nazi Party [[Nazi Party|NSDAP]]. Habermas himself was a ''Jungvolkführer'', a leader of the [[Deutsches Jungvolk|German Jungvolk]], which was a section of the [[Hitler Youth]]. He was brought up in a staunchly [[Protestant]] [[milieu]], his grandfather being the director of the seminary in Gummersbach. He studied at the universities of [[University of Göttingen|Göttingen]] (1949/50), [[University of Zurich|Zurich]] (1950/51), and [[University of Bonn|Bonn]] (1951–54) and earned a doctorate in [[philosophy]] from Bonn in 1954 with a dissertation written on the conflict between "the Absolute" and [[history]] in [[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling|Schelling]]'s thought, entitled, ''{{lang|de|Das Absolute und die Geschichte. Von der Zwiespältigkeit in Schellings Denken}}'' ("The Absolute and History: On the Schism in Schelling's Thought").<ref name="Habermas p. ">{{cite journal | last=Habermas |first=Jürgen |title=Das Absolute und die Geschichte |trans-title=The Absolute and History |journal=University Library Heidelberg |year=1954 |doi=10.11588/DIGLIT.41402 |url=https://digi.ub.uni-heidelberg.de/diglit/habermas1954 |language=de |access-date=3 December 2022 |page=}}</ref> His dissertation committee included [[Erich Rothacker]] and [[Oskar Becker]].<ref name="Habermas p. " />


From 1956 on, he studied [[philosophy]] and [[sociology]] under the [[critical theorists]] [[Max Horkheimer]] and [[Theodor W. Adorno]] at the [[Goethe University Frankfurt]]'s [[Institute for Social Research]], but because of a rift between the two over his [[dissertation]]—Horkheimer had made unacceptable demands for revision—as well as his own belief that the [[Frankfurt School]] had become paralyzed with political skepticism and disdain for [[modern culture]],<ref name=cjc352>Craig J. Calhoun, ''Contemporary Sociological Theory'', Wiley-Blackwell, 2002, p. 352. {{ISBN|0-631-21350-3}}.</ref> he finished his [[habilitation]] in [[political science]] at the [[University of Marburg]] under the Marxist [[Wolfgang Abendroth]]. His habilitation work was entitled ''{{lang|de|Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit. Untersuchungen zu einer Kategorie der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft}}'' (published in English translation in 1989 as ''[[The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere]]: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society''). It is a detailed social history of the development of the [[bourgeois]] [[public sphere]] from its origins in the 18th century salons up to its transformation through the influence of capital-driven [[mass media]]. In 1961 he became a ''[[Privatdozent]]'' in Marburg, and—in a move that was highly unusual for the German academic scene of that time—he was offered the position of "extraordinary professor" (professor without chair) of philosophy at the [[University of Heidelberg]] (at the instigation of [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]] and [[Karl Löwith]]) in 1962, which he accepted. In this same year he gained his first serious public attention, in Germany, with the publication of his habilitation. In 1964, strongly supported by Adorno, Habermas returned to Frankfurt to take over Horkheimer's chair in philosophy and sociology. The philosopher [[Albrecht Wellmer]] was his assistant in Frankfurt from 1966 to 1970.
From 1956 on, he studied [[philosophy]] and [[sociology]] under the [[critical theorists]] [[Max Horkheimer]] and [[Theodor W. Adorno]] at the [[Goethe University Frankfurt]]'s [[Institute for Social Research]], but because of a rift between the two over his [[dissertation]]—Horkheimer had made unacceptable demands for revision—as well as his own belief that the [[Frankfurt School]] had become paralyzed with political skepticism and disdain for [[modern culture]],<ref name=cjc352>{{cite book |first=Craig J. |last=Calhoun |title=Contemporary Sociological Theory |publisher=[[Wiley-Blackwell]] |date=2002 |page=352 |isbn=0-631-21350-3}}</ref> he finished his [[habilitation]] in [[political science]] at the [[University of Marburg]] under the Marxist [[Wolfgang Abendroth]]. His habilitation work was entitled ''{{lang|de|Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit. Untersuchungen zu einer Kategorie der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft}}'' (published in English translation in 1989 as ''[[The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere]]: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society''). It is a detailed social history of the development of the [[bourgeois]] [[public sphere]] from its origins in the 18th century salons up to its transformation through the influence of capital-driven [[mass media]]. In 1961 he became a ''[[Privatdozent]]'' in Marburg, and—in a move that was highly unusual for the German academic scene of that time—he was offered the position of "extraordinary professor" (professor without chair) of philosophy at the [[University of Heidelberg]] (at the instigation of [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]] and [[Karl Löwith]]) in 1962, which he accepted. In this same year he gained his first serious public attention, in Germany, with the publication of his habilitation. In 1964, strongly supported by Adorno, Habermas returned to Frankfurt to take over Horkheimer's chair in philosophy and sociology. The philosopher [[Albrecht Wellmer]] was his assistant in Frankfurt from 1966 to 1970.


He accepted the position of Director of the [[Max Planck Institute#Former institutes|Max Planck Institute for the Study of the Scientific-Technical World]] in [[Starnberg]] (near [[Munich]]) in 1971, and worked there until 1983, two years after the publication of his [[Masterpiece|magnum opus]], ''[[The Theory of Communicative Action]]''. He was elected a Foreign Honorary Member of the [[American Academy of Arts and Sciences]] in 1984.<ref name=AAAS>{{cite web|title=Book of Members, 1780–2010: Chapter H|url=http://www.amacad.org/publications/BookofMembers/ChapterH.pdf|publisher=American Academy of Arts and Sciences|access-date=19 April 2011}}</ref>
He accepted the position of Director of the [[Max Planck Institute#Former institutes|Max Planck Institute for the Study of the Scientific-Technical World]] in [[Starnberg]] (near [[Munich]]) in 1971, and worked there until 1983, two years after the publication of his [[Masterpiece|magnum opus]], ''[[The Theory of Communicative Action]]''. He was elected a Foreign Honorary Member of the [[American Academy of Arts and Sciences]] in 1984.<ref name=AAAS>{{cite web |title=Book of Members, 1780–2010: Chapter H |url=http://www.amacad.org/publications/BookofMembers/ChapterH.pd f|publisher=American Academy of Arts and Sciences |access-date=19 April 2011 |archive-url= |archive-date=}}</ref>


Habermas then returned to his chair at Frankfurt and the directorship of the Institute for Social Research. Since retiring from Frankfurt in 1993, Habermas has continued to publish extensively. In 1986, he received the [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Prize]] of the {{lang|de|[[Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft]]}}, which is the highest honour awarded in German research. He also holds the position of "permanent visiting" professor at [[Northwestern University]] in Evanston, Illinois, and "[[Theodor Heuss]] Professor" at [[The New School]], [[New York City|New York]].
Habermas then returned to his chair at Frankfurt and the directorship of the Institute for Social Research. Since retiring from Frankfurt in 1993, Habermas has continued to publish extensively. In 1986, he received the [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Prize]] of the {{lang|de|[[Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft]]}}, which is the highest honour awarded in German research. He also holds the position of "permanent visiting" professor at [[Northwestern University]] in Evanston, Illinois, and "[[Theodor Heuss]] Professor" at [[The New School]], [[New York City|New York]].


Habermas was awarded the [[Prince of Asturias Award]] in Social Sciences of 2003. Habermas was also the 2004 Kyoto Laureate<ref>Jürgen Habermas (2004) [http://homepage.mac.com/gedavis/JH/Kyoto_lecture_Nov_2004.pdf Public space and political public sphere – the biographical roots of two motifs in my thought.](Commemorative Lecture, Kyoto) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120204151440/http://homepage.mac.com/gedavis/JH/Kyoto_lecture_Nov_2004.pdf|date=4 February 2012}} (pp. 2–4)</ref> in the [[Kyoto Prize in Arts and Philosophy|Arts and Philosophy]] section. He traveled to [[San Diego]] and on 5 March 2005, as part of the [[University of San Diego]]'s Kyoto Symposium, gave a speech entitled ''The Public Role of Religion in Secular Context'', regarding the evolution of [[separation of church and state]] from neutrality to intense [[secularism]]. He received the 2005 [[Holberg International Memorial Prize]] (about €520,000). In 2007, Habermas was listed as the seventh most-cited author in the [[humanities]] (including the [[social science]]s) by ''[[The Times Higher Education Guide]]'', ahead of Max Weber and behind [[Erving Goffman]].<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.timeshighereducation.co.uk/story.asp?storyCode=405956&sectioncode=26 |title=The most cited authors of books in the humanities |publisher=timeshighereducation.co.uk |date=26 March 2009 |access-date=16 November 2009}}</ref> [[Bibliometrics|Bibliometric]] studies demonstrate his continuing influence and increasing relevance.<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Buhmann|first1=Alexander|last2=Ihlen|first2=Øyvind|last3=Aaen-Stockdale|first3=Craig|date=2019-11-04|title=Connecting the dots: a bibliometric review of Habermasian theory in public relations research|url=https://www.emerald.com/insight/content/doi/10.1108/JCOM-12-2018-0127/full/html|journal=Journal of Communication Management|language=en|volume=23|issue=4|pages=444–467|doi=10.1108/JCOM-12-2018-0127|hdl=10852/74987|s2cid=210568613|issn=1363-254X|hdl-access=free}}</ref>
Habermas was awarded the [[Prince of Asturias Award]] in Social Sciences of 2003. Habermas was also the 2004 Kyoto Laureate<ref>Jürgen Habermas (2004) [http://homepage.mac.com/gedavis/JH/Kyoto_lecture_Nov_2004.pdf Public space and political public sphere – the biographical roots of two motifs in my thought.](Commemorative Lecture, Kyoto) {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120204151440/http://homepage.mac.com/gedavis/JH/Kyoto_lecture_Nov_2004.pdf|date=4 February 2012}} (pp. 2–4)</ref> in the [[Kyoto Prize in Arts and Philosophy|Arts and Philosophy]] section. He traveled to [[San Diego]] and on 5 March 2005, as part of the [[University of San Diego]]'s Kyoto Symposium, gave a speech entitled ''The Public Role of Religion in Secular Context'', regarding the evolution of [[separation of church and state]] from neutrality to intense [[secularism]]. He received the 2005 [[Holberg International Memorial Prize]] (about €520,000). In 2007, Habermas was listed as the seventh most-cited author in the [[humanities]] (including the [[social science]]s) by ''[[The Times Higher Education Guide]]'', ahead of Max Weber and behind [[Erving Goffman]].<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.timeshighereducation.co.uk/story.asp?storyCode=405956&sectioncode=26 |title=The most cited authors of books in the humanities |publisher=timeshighereducation.co.uk |date=26 March 2009 |access-date=16 November 2009 |archive-url= |archive-date=}}</ref> [[Bibliometrics|Bibliometric]] studies demonstrate his continuing influence and increasing relevance.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Buhmann |first1=Alexander |last2=Ihlen |first2=Øyvind |last3=Aaen-Stockdale |first3=Craig |date=4 November 2019 |title=Connecting the dots: a bibliometric review of Habermasian theory in public relations research |url=https://www.emerald.com/insight/content/doi/10.1108/JCOM-12-2018-0127/full/html |journal=[[Journal of Communication Management]] |language=en |volume=23 |issue=4 |pages=444–467 |doi=10.1108/JCOM-12-2018-0127 |hdl=10852/74987 |s2cid=210568613 |issn=1363-254X |hdl-access=free}}</ref>


Jürgen Habermas is the father of [[Rebekka Habermas]], historian of German social and cultural history and professor of modern history at the [[University of Göttingen]].
Jürgen Habermas was the father of [[Rebekka Habermas]] (1959–2023), historian of German social and cultural history and professor of modern history at the [[University of Göttingen]].


===Teacher and mentor===
===Teacher and mentor===
Habermas was a famed teacher and mentor. Among his most prominent students were the pragmatic philosopher Herbert Schnädelbach (theorist of discourse distinction and rationality), the political sociologist [[Claus Offe]] (professor at the [[Hertie School of Governance]] in Berlin), the social philosopher Johann Arnason (professor at [[La Trobe University]] and chief editor of the journal ''[[Thesis Eleven]]''), the social philosopher [[Hans-Herbert Kögler]] (Chair of Philosophy at the [[University of North Florida]]), the sociological theorist [[Hans Joas]] (professor at the [[University of Erfurt]] and at the [[University of Chicago]]), the theorist of societal [[evolution]] Klaus Eder, the social philosopher [[Axel Honneth]], the political theorist David Rasmussen (professor at [[Boston College]] and chief editor of the journal "[[Philosophy & Social Criticism]]"), the environmental ethicist [[Konrad Ott]], the anarcho-capitalist philosopher [[Hans-Hermann Hoppe]] (who came to reject much of Habermas's thought),<ref>[[Lew Rockwell]], introduction to Hoppe's ''A Short History of Man'' (2015), Auburn, Mississippi: Mises Institute, p. 9.</ref> the American philosopher [[Thomas A. McCarthy|Thomas McCarthy]], the co-creator of mindful inquiry in social research [[Jeremy J. Shapiro]], the political philosopher [[Cristina Lafont]] (Harold H. and Virginia Anderson Professor of Philosophy at [[Northwestern University]]), and the assassinated Serbian prime minister [[Zoran Đinđić]].
Habermas was a famed teacher and mentor. Among his most prominent students were the pragmatic philosopher Herbert Schnädelbach (theorist of discourse distinction and rationality), the political sociologist [[Claus Offe]] (professor at the [[Hertie School of Governance]] in Berlin), the social philosopher Johann Arnason (professor at [[La Trobe University]] and chief editor of the journal ''[[Thesis Eleven]]''), the social philosopher [[Hans-Herbert Kögler]] (Chair of Philosophy at the [[University of North Florida]]), the sociological theorist [[Hans Joas]] (professor at the [[University of Erfurt]] and at the [[University of Chicago]]), the theorist of societal [[evolution]] Klaus Eder, the social philosopher [[Axel Honneth]], the political theorist David Rasmussen (professor at [[Boston College]] and chief editor of the journal ''[[Philosophy & Social Criticism]]''), the environmental ethicist [[Konrad Ott]], the anarcho-capitalist philosopher [[Hans-Hermann Hoppe]] (who came to reject much of Habermas's thought),<ref>[[Lew Rockwell]], introduction to Hoppe's ''A Short History of Man'' (2015), Auburn, Mississippi: Mises Institute, p. 9.</ref> the American philosopher [[Thomas A. McCarthy|Thomas McCarthy]], the co-creator of mindful inquiry in social research [[Jeremy J. Shapiro]], the political philosopher [[Cristina Lafont]] (Harold H. and Virginia Anderson Professor of Philosophy at [[Northwestern University]]), and the assassinated Serbian prime minister [[Zoran Đinđić]].


==Philosophy and social theory==
==Philosophy and social theory==
Habermas has constructed a comprehensive framework of philosophy and social theory drawing on a number of intellectual traditions:<ref name="Habermas, Jurgen 1981">Habermas, Jurgen (1981), ''Kleine Politische Schrifen I-IV'', pp. 500f.</ref>
Habermas has constructed a comprehensive framework of philosophy and social theory drawing on a number of intellectual traditions:<ref name="Habermas, Jurgen 1981">{{cite book |last=Habermas |first=Jürgen |date=1981 |title=Kleine Politische Schrifen I-IV |language=de |page=500}}</ref>
* the [[German philosophy|German philosophical thought]] of [[Immanuel Kant]], [[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling|Friedrich Schelling]], [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|G. W. F. Hegel]], [[Wilhelm Dilthey]], [[Edmund Husserl]] and [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]]
* the [[German philosophy|German philosophical thought]] of [[Immanuel Kant]], [[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling|Friedrich Schelling]], [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|G. W. F. Hegel]], [[Wilhelm Dilthey]], [[Edmund Husserl]] and [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]]
* the [[Marxist philosophy|Marxian]] tradition—both the theory of [[Karl Marx]] himself as well as the critical [[Neo-Marxism|neo-Marxian]] theory of the [[Frankfurt School]], i.e. [[Max Horkheimer]], [[Theodor Adorno]] and [[Herbert Marcuse]].<ref name="Habermas, Jurgen 1981"/>
* the [[Marxist philosophy|Marxian]] tradition—both the theory of [[Karl Marx]] himself as well as the critical [[Neo-Marxism|neo-Marxian]] theory of the [[Frankfurt School]], i.e. [[Max Horkheimer]], [[Theodor Adorno]] and [[Herbert Marcuse]].<ref name="Habermas, Jurgen 1981"/>
Line 78: Line 75:
* the American pragmatist tradition of [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] and [[John Dewey]]
* the American pragmatist tradition of [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] and [[John Dewey]]
* the sociological [[social system|social systems theory]] of [[Talcott Parsons]] and [[Niklas Luhmann]]
* the sociological [[social system|social systems theory]] of [[Talcott Parsons]] and [[Niklas Luhmann]]
* [[Neo-Kantian]] thought<ref>Müller-Doohm, Stefan. Jürgen Habermas. Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, 2008 (Suhrkamp BasisBiographie, 38).</ref>
* [[Neo-Kantian]] thought<ref>{{cite book |last=Müller-Doohm |first=Stefan |title=Jürgen Habermas |location=Frankfurt |publisher=Suhrkamp |date=2008 |series=Suhrkamp BasisBiographie |volume=38}}</ref>


Jürgen Habermas considers his major contribution to be the development of the concept and theory of communicative reason or communicative rationality, which distinguishes itself from the [[rationalism|rationalist tradition]], by locating [[rationality]] in structures of interpersonal linguistic [[communication]] rather than in the structure of the [[cosmos]]. This social theory advances the goals of [[human emancipation]], while maintaining an inclusive [[universalist]] [[morality|moral]] framework. This framework rests on the argument called [[universal pragmatics]]—that all [[speech acts]] have an inherent [[Telos (philosophy)|telos]] (the [[Greek language|Greek]] word for "purpose")—the goal of mutual [[understanding]], and that human beings possess the communicative competence to bring about such understanding. Habermas built the framework out of the [[speech-act]] philosophy of [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], [[J. L. Austin]] and [[John Searle]], the sociological theory of the interactional constitution of mind and self of [[George Herbert Mead]], the [[moral development|theories of moral development]] of [[Jean Piaget]] and [[Lawrence Kohlberg]], and the [[discourse ethics]] of his Frankfurt colleague and fellow student [[Karl-Otto Apel]].
Jürgen Habermas considers his major contribution to be the development of the concept and theory of communicative reason or communicative rationality, which distinguishes itself from the [[rationalism|rationalist tradition]], by locating [[rationality]] in structures of interpersonal linguistic [[communication]] rather than in the structure of the [[cosmos]]. This social theory advances the goals of [[human emancipation]], while maintaining an inclusive [[universalist]] [[morality|moral]] framework. This framework rests on the argument called [[universal pragmatics]]—that all [[speech acts]] have an inherent [[Telos (philosophy)|telos]] (the [[Greek language|Greek]] word for "purpose")—the goal of mutual [[understanding]], and that human beings possess the communicative competence to bring about such understanding. Habermas built the framework out of the [[speech-act]] philosophy of [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], [[J. L. Austin]] and [[John Searle]], the sociological theory of the interactional constitution of mind and self of [[George Herbert Mead]], the [[moral development|theories of moral development]] of [[Jean Piaget]] and [[Lawrence Kohlberg]], and the [[discourse ethics]] of his Frankfurt colleague and fellow student [[Karl-Otto Apel]].


Habermas's works resonate within the traditions of Kant and [[the Enlightenment]] and of [[democratic socialism]] through his emphasis on the potential for transforming the world and arriving at a more humane, just, and egalitarian society through the realization of the human potential for reason, in part through discourse ethics. While Habermas has stated that the Enlightenment is an "unfinished project," he argues it should be corrected and complemented, not discarded.<ref name=cjc351>Calhoun (2002), p. 351.</ref> In this he distances himself from the Frankfurt School, criticizing it, as well as much of [[postmodernist]] thought, for excessive pessimism, [[Political radicalism|radicalism]], and exaggerations.<ref name=cjc351/>
Habermas's works resonate within the traditions of Kant and [[the Enlightenment]] and of [[democratic socialism]] through his emphasis on the potential for transforming the world and arriving at a more humane, just, and egalitarian society through the realization of the human potential for reason, in part through discourse ethics. While Habermas has stated that the Enlightenment is an "unfinished project," he argues it should be corrected and complemented, not discarded.<ref name=cjc351>{{harvnb|Calhoun|2002|p=351}}</ref> In this he distances himself from the Frankfurt School, criticizing it, as well as much of [[postmodernist]] thought, for excessive pessimism, [[Political radicalism|radicalism]], and exaggerations.<ref name=cjc351/>


Within sociology, Habermas's major contribution was the development of a comprehensive theory of [[societal evolution]] and [[modernization]] focusing on the difference between communicative rationality and rationalization on one hand and strategic/[[instrumental rationality]] and rationalization on the other. This includes a critique from a communicative standpoint of the differentiation-based [[theory]] of [[social system]]s developed by [[Niklas Luhmann]], a student of [[Talcott Parsons]].
Within sociology, Habermas's major contribution was the development of a comprehensive theory of [[societal evolution]] and [[modernization]] focusing on the difference between communicative rationality and rationalization on one hand and strategic/[[instrumental rationality]] and rationalization on the other. This includes a critique from a communicative standpoint of the differentiation-based [[theory]] of [[social system]]s developed by [[Niklas Luhmann]], a student of [[Talcott Parsons]].
Line 96: Line 93:


This model finds an application, above all, in the "theory of the social evolution", starting from the reconstruction of the necessary conditions for a [[Phylogenetic tree|phylogeny]] of the socio-cultural life forms (the "hominization") until an analysis of the development of "social formations", which Habermas subdivides into primitive, traditional, modern and contemporary formations.
This model finds an application, above all, in the "theory of the social evolution", starting from the reconstruction of the necessary conditions for a [[Phylogenetic tree|phylogeny]] of the socio-cultural life forms (the "hominization") until an analysis of the development of "social formations", which Habermas subdivides into primitive, traditional, modern and contemporary formations.
"This paper is an attempt, primarily, to formalize the model of "reconstruction of the logic of development" of "social formations" summed up by Habermas through the differentiation between vital world and social systems (and, within them, through the "rationalization of the world of life" and the "growth in complexity of the social systems"). Secondly, it tries to offer some methodological clarifications about the "explanation of the dynamics" of "historical processes" and, in particular, about the "theoretical meaning" of the evolutional theory's propositions. Even if the German sociologist considers that the "ex-post rational reconstructions" and "the models system/environment" cannot have a complete "historiographical application", these certainly act as a general premise in the argumentative structure of the "historical explanation"".<ref name="Corchia">{{citation | first = Luca | last = Corchia | chapter = Explicative models of complexity. The reconstructions of social evolution for Jürgen Habermas | editor1-first = S | editor-last = Balbi | editor2-first = G | editor2-last = Scepi | editor3-first = G | editor3-last = Russolillo | editor4-first = A |display-editors = 3 | editor4-last = Stawinoga | chapter-url = http://www.jovene.it/articoli/details.php?nome=Catalogo&ID=38140&Tipo=listino&Oggetto=Novit%C3%A0 | title = Book of Short Abstracts | volume = 7th International Conference on Social Science Methodology&nbsp;– RC33&nbsp;– Logic and Methodology in Sociology | place = Napoli, IT | date = 1 September 2008 | publisher = Jovene Editore }}</ref>
"This paper is an attempt, primarily, to formalize the model of "reconstruction of the logic of development" of "social formations" summed up by Habermas through the differentiation between vital world and social systems (and, within them, through the "rationalization of the world of life" and the "growth in complexity of the social systems"). Secondly, it tries to offer some methodological clarifications about the "explanation of the dynamics" of "historical processes" and, in particular, about the "theoretical meaning" of the evolutional theory's propositions. Even if the German sociologist considers that the "ex-post rational reconstructions" and "the models system/environment" cannot have a complete "historiographical application", these certainly act as a general premise in the argumentative structure of the "historical explanation".<ref name="Corchia">{{cite book |first=Luca |last=Corchia |chapter=Explicative models of complexity. The reconstructions of social evolution for Jürgen Habermas |editor1-first=S |editor-last=Balbi |editor2-first=G |editor2-last=Scepi |editor3-first=G |editor3-last=Russolillo |editor4-first=A |display-editors=3 |editor4-last=Stawinoga |chapter-url=http://www.jovene.it/articoli/details.php?nome=Catalogo&ID=38140&Tipo=listino&Oggetto=Novit%C3%A0 |title=Book of Short Abstracts |volume=7th International Conference on Social Science Methodology&nbsp;– RC33&nbsp;– Logic and Methodology in Sociology |place=Napoli, IT |date=1 September 2008 |publisher=Jovene Editore}}</ref>


===The public sphere===
===The public sphere===
{{further|Public sphere}}
{{further|Public sphere}}
In ''[[The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere]],'' Habermas argues that prior to the 18th century, European culture had been dominated by a "representational" culture, where one party sought to "represent" itself on its audience by overwhelming its subjects.<ref name=Blanning26>Blanning, T. C. W. ''The French Revolution Class War or Culture Clash?'', New York: St. Martin's Press (1987), 2nd edition 1998, p. 26.</ref> As an example of "representational" culture, Habermas argued that [[Louis XIV of France|Louis XIV]]'s [[Palace of Versailles]] was meant to show the greatness of the French state and its King by overpowering the senses of visitors to the Palace.<ref name=Blanning26 /> Habermas identifies "representational" culture as corresponding to the feudal stage of development according to Marxist theory, arguing that the coming of the capitalist stage of development marked the appearance of ''Öffentlichkeit'' (the public sphere).<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. pages 26-27">Blanning (1998), pp. 26–27.</ref> In the culture characterized by ''Öffentlichkeit'', there occurred a public space outside of the control by the state, where individuals exchanged views and knowledge.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27">Blanning (1998), p. 27.</ref>
In ''[[The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere]],'' Habermas argues that prior to the 18th century, European culture had been dominated by a "representational" culture, where one party sought to "represent" itself on its audience by overwhelming its subjects.<ref name=Blanning26>{{cite book |last=Blanning |first=T. C. W. |title=The French Revolution Class War or Culture Clash? |location=New York |publisher=St. Martin's Press |orig-date=1987 |edition=2nd |date=1998 |page=26}}</ref> As an example of "representational" culture, Habermas argued that [[Louis XIV of France|Louis XIV]]'s [[Palace of Versailles]] was meant to show the greatness of the French state and its King by overpowering the senses of visitors to the Palace.<ref name=Blanning26 /> Habermas identifies "representational" culture as corresponding to the feudal stage of development according to Marxist theory, arguing that the coming of the capitalist stage of development marked the appearance of {{lang|de|Öffentlichkeit}} (the public sphere).<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. pages 26-27">{{harvnb|Blanning|1998|pp=26–27}}</ref> In the culture characterized by {{lang|de|Öffentlichkeit}}, there occurred a public space outside of the control by the state, where individuals exchanged views and knowledge.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27">{{harvnb|Blanning|1998|p=27}}</ref>


In Habermas's view, the growth in [[newspaper]]s, [[Literary magazine|journals]], reading clubs, [[Masonic lodge]]s, and [[coffeehouse]]s in 18th-century Europe, all in different ways, marked the gradual replacement of "representational" culture with ''Öffentlichkeit'' culture.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27" /> Habermas argued that the essential characteristic of the ''Öffentlichkeit'' culture was its "critical" nature.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27" /> Unlike "representational" culture where only one party was active and the other passive, the ''Öffentlichkeit'' culture was characterized by a dialogue as individuals either met in conversation, or exchanged views via the print media.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27" /> Habermas maintains that as Britain was the most liberal country in Europe, the culture of the public sphere emerged there first around 1700, and the growth of ''Öffentlichkeit'' culture took place over most of the 18th century in Continental Europe.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27" /> In his view, the [[French Revolution]] was in large part caused by the collapse of "representational" culture, and its replacement by ''Öffentlichkeit'' culture.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27" /> Though Habermas's main concern in ''The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere'' was to expose what he regarded as the deceptive nature of free institutions in the West, his book had a major effect on the historiography of the French Revolution.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. pages 26-27" />
In Habermas's view, the growth in [[newspaper]]s, [[Literary magazine|journals]], reading clubs, [[Masonic lodge]]s, and [[coffeehouse]]s in 18th-century Europe, all in different ways, marked the gradual replacement of "representational" culture with {{lang|de|Öffentlichkeit}} culture.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27" /> Habermas argued that the essential characteristic of the {{lang|de|Öffentlichkeit}} culture was its "critical" nature.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27" /> Unlike "representational" culture where only one party was active and the other passive, the {{lang|de|Öffentlichkeit}} culture was characterized by a dialogue as individuals either met in conversation, or exchanged views via the print media.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27" /> Habermas maintains that as Britain was the most liberal country in Europe, the culture of the public sphere emerged there first around 1700, and the growth of {{lang|de|Öffentlichkeit}} culture took place over most of the 18th century in Continental Europe.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27" /> In his view, the [[French Revolution]] was in large part caused by the collapse of "representational" culture, and its replacement by {{lang|de|Öffentlichkeit}} culture.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. page 27" /> Though Habermas's main concern in ''The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere'' was to expose what he regarded as the deceptive nature of free institutions in the West, his book had a major effect on the historiography of the French Revolution.<ref name="Blanning, T.C.W. pages 26-27" />


According to Habermas, a variety of factors resulted in the eventual decay of the public sphere, including the growth of a [[commerce|commercial]] [[mass media]], which turned the critical public into a passive consumer public; and the welfare state, which merged the state with society so thoroughly that the public sphere was squeezed out. It also turned the "public sphere" into a site of self-interested contestation for the resources of the state rather than a space for the development of a public-minded [[rational consensus]].
According to Habermas, a variety of factors resulted in the eventual decay of the public sphere, including the growth of a [[commerce|commercial]] [[mass media]], which turned the critical public into a passive consumer public; and the welfare state, which merged the state with society so thoroughly that the public sphere was squeezed out. It also turned the "public sphere" into a site of self-interested contestation for the resources of the state rather than a space for the development of a public-minded [[rational consensus]].


His most known work to date, the ''[[Theory of Communicative Action]]'' (1981), is based on an adaptation of Talcott Parsons [[AGIL Paradigm]]. In this work, Habermas voiced criticism of the process of modernization, which he saw as inflexible direction forced through by economic and administrative rationalization.<ref name=cjc353>Calhoun (2002), p. 353.</ref> Habermas outlined how our everyday lives are penetrated by formal systems as parallel to development of the [[welfare state]], [[corporate capitalism]] and [[mass consumption]].<ref name=cjc353/> These reinforcing trends rationalize public life.<ref name=cjc353/> Disfranchisement of citizens occurs as political parties and interest groups become rationalized and [[representative democracy]] replaces [[participatory democracy|participatory one]].<ref name=cjc353/> In consequence, boundaries between public and private, the individual and society, the [[Social system|system]] and the lifeworld are deteriorating.<ref name=cjc353/> Democratic public life cannot develop where matters of public importance are not discussed by citizens.<ref name=cjc354>Calhoun (2002), p. 354.</ref> An "[[ideal speech situation]]"<ref>{{cite book |title=Democracy, Power and Legitimacy: The Critical Theory of Jürgen Habermas |last=Payrow Shabani |first=Omid A. |year=2003 |publisher=University of Toronto Press |isbn= 978-0-8020-8761-4 |page=49 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=tKDU3l3cq60C&pg=PA49}}</ref> requires participants to have the same capacities of discourse, social equality and their words are not confused by ideology or other errors.<ref name=cjc354/> In this version of the [[consensus theory of truth]] Habermas maintains that truth is what would be agreed upon in an ideal speech situation.
His most known work to date, the ''[[Theory of Communicative Action]]'' (1981), is based on an adaptation of Talcott Parsons [[AGIL Paradigm]]. In this work, Habermas voiced criticism of the process of modernization, which he saw as inflexible direction forced through by economic and administrative rationalization.<ref name=cjc353>{{harvnb|Calhoun|2002|p=353}}</ref> Habermas outlined how our everyday lives are penetrated by formal systems as parallel to development of the [[welfare state]], [[corporate capitalism]] and [[mass consumption]].<ref name=cjc353/> These reinforcing trends rationalize public life.<ref name=cjc353/> Disfranchisement of citizens occurs as political parties and interest groups become rationalized and [[representative democracy]] replaces [[participatory democracy|participatory one]].<ref name=cjc353/> In consequence, boundaries between public and private, the individual and society, the [[Social system|system]] and the lifeworld are deteriorating.<ref name=cjc353/> Democratic public life cannot develop where matters of public importance are not discussed by citizens.<ref name=cjc354>{{harvnb|Calhoun|2002|p=354}}</ref> An "[[ideal speech situation]]"<ref>{{cite book |title=Democracy, Power and Legitimacy: The Critical Theory of Jürgen Habermas |last=Payrow Shabani |first=Omid A. |year=2003 |publisher=University of Toronto Press |isbn= 978-0-8020-8761-4 |page=49 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=tKDU3l3cq60C&pg=PA49}}</ref> requires participants to have the same capacities of discourse, social equality and their words are not confused by ideology or other errors.<ref name=cjc354/> In this version of the [[consensus theory of truth]] Habermas maintains that truth is what would be agreed upon in an ideal speech situation.


Habermas has expressed optimism about the possibility of the revival of the public sphere.<ref name=cjc355>Calhoun (2002), p. 355.</ref> He discerns a hope for the future where the representative democracy-reliant [[nation-state]] is replaced by a [[deliberative democracy]]-reliant political organism based on the equal rights and obligations of citizens.<ref name=cjc355/> In such a direct democracy-driven system, the activist public sphere is needed for debates on matters of public importance as well as the mechanism for that discussion to affect the [[decision-making process]].
Habermas has expressed optimism about the possibility of the revival of the public sphere.<ref name=cjc355>{{harvnb|Calhoun|2002|p=355}}</ref> He discerns a hope for the future where the representative democracy-reliant [[nation-state]] is replaced by a [[deliberative democracy]]-reliant political organism based on the equal rights and obligations of citizens.<ref name=cjc355/> In such a direct democracy-driven system, the activist public sphere is needed for debates on matters of public importance as well as the mechanism for that discussion to affect the [[decision-making process]].


==Habermas versus postmodernists==
==Habermas versus postmodernists==
Habermas offered some early criticisms in an essay, "Modernity versus Postmodernity" (1981),<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Habermas|first1=Jürgen|last2=Ben-Habib|first2=Seyla|date=1981|title=Modernity versus Postmodernity|journal=New German Critique|issue=22|pages=3–14|doi=10.2307/487859|jstor=487859|issn=0094-033X}}</ref> which has achieved wide recognition. In that essay, Habermas raises the issue of whether, in light of the failures of the twentieth century, we "should try to hold on to the ''intentions of the Enlightenment'', feeble as they may be, or should we declare the entire project of modernity a lost cause?"<ref name="Ritzer, George Pg. 567-568">Ritzer, George, ''Sociological Theory'', ''From Modern to Postmodern Social Theory (and Beyond)'', McGraw-Hill Higher Education, New York, New York, 2008, pp. 567–568.</ref> Habermas refuses to give up on the possibility of a rational, "scientific" understanding of the life-world.
Habermas offered some early criticisms in an essay, "Modernity versus Postmodernity" (1981),<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Habermas |first1=Jürgen |last2=Ben-Habib |first2=Seyla |date=1981 |title=Modernity versus Postmodernity |journal=[[New German Critique]] |issue=22 |pages=3–14 |doi=10.2307/487859 |jstor=487859 |issn=0094-033X}}</ref> which has achieved wide recognition. In that essay, Habermas raises the issue of whether, in light of the failures of the twentieth century, we "should try to hold on to the ''intentions of the Enlightenment'', feeble as they may be, or should we declare the entire project of modernity a lost cause?"<ref name="Ritzer, George Pg. 567-568">{{cite book |last=Ritzer |first=George |chapter=Sociological Theory |title=From Modern to Postmodern Social Theory (and Beyond) |publisher=[[McGraw-Hill]] |location=New York, New York |date=2008 |pages=567–568}}</ref> Habermas refuses to give up on the possibility of a rational, "scientific" understanding of the life-world.


Habermas has several main criticisms of [[postmodernism]]:
Habermas has several main criticisms of [[postmodernism]]:
Line 126: Line 123:


=== Habermas and Gadamer ===
=== Habermas and Gadamer ===
There is a controversy between Habermas and [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]] about limits of [[hermeneutics]]. Gadamer completed his magnum opus, ''Truth and Method'' in 1960, and engaged in his debate with Habermas over the possibility of transcending history and culture in order to find a truly objective position from which to critique society.
There is a controversy between Habermas and [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]] about limits of [[hermeneutics]]. Gadamer completed his magnum opus, ''Truth and Method'', in 1960, and engaged in his debate with Habermas over the possibility of transcending history and culture in order to find a truly objective position from which to critique society.


During the 1960s, Gadamer supported Habermas and advocated for him to be offered a job at Heidelberg before he had completed his Habilitation, despite Max Horkheimer's objections. While they both criticized positivism, a philosophical disagreement arose between them in the 1970s. This disagreement expanded the scope of Gadamer's philosophical influence. Despite fundamental agreements between them, such as starting from the hermeneutic tradition and returning to Greek practical philosophy, Habermas argued that Gadamer's emphasis on tradition and prejudice blinded him to the ideological operation of power. Habermas believed that Gadamer's approach failed to enable critical reflection on the sources of ideology in society. He accused Gadamer of endorsing a dogmatic stance toward tradition, which made it difficult to identify distortions in understanding. Gadamer countered that refusing the universal nature of hermeneutics was the more dogmatic stance because it affirmed the deception that the subject can free itself from the past.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Barthold |first1=Lauren Swayne |title=Hans-Georg Gadamer (1900—2002) |url=https://iep.utm.edu/gadamer/ |website=Internet Encylopedia of Philosophy |access-date=22 February 2023}}</ref>
During the 1960s, Gadamer supported Habermas and advocated for him to be offered a job at Heidelberg before he had completed his Habilitation, despite Max Horkheimer's objections. While they both criticized positivism, a philosophical disagreement arose between them in the 1970s. This disagreement expanded the scope of Gadamer's philosophical influence. Despite fundamental agreements between them, such as starting from the hermeneutic tradition and returning to Greek practical philosophy, Habermas argued that Gadamer's emphasis on tradition and prejudice blinded him to the ideological operation of power. Habermas believed that Gadamer's approach failed to enable critical reflection on the sources of ideology in society. He accused Gadamer of endorsing a dogmatic stance toward tradition, which made it difficult to identify distortions in understanding. Gadamer countered that refusing the universal nature of hermeneutics was the more dogmatic stance because it affirmed the deception that the subject can free itself from the past.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Barthold |first1=Lauren Swayne |title=Hans-Georg Gadamer (1900—2002) |url=https://iep.utm.edu/gadamer/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=22 February 2023}}</ref>


=== Habermas and Foucault ===
=== Habermas and Foucault ===
Line 138: Line 135:


=== Habermas and Apel ===
=== Habermas and Apel ===
Habermas and [[Karl-Otto Apel]] both support a postmetaphysical, universal moral theory, but they disagree on the nature and justification of this principle. Habermas disagrees with Apel's view that the principle is a transcendental condition of human activity, while Apel asserts that it is. They each criticize the other's position. Habermas argues that Apel is too concerned with transcendental conditions, while Apel argues that Habermas doesn't value critical discourse enough.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gamwell |first1=Franklin I. |title=Habermas and Apel on communicative ethics: Their difference and the difference it makes |journal=Philosophy and Social Criticism |date=1997 |volume=23 |issue=2 |pages=21–45 |doi=10.1177/019145379702300202 |s2cid=144776550 |url=https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/019145379702300202}}</ref>
Habermas and [[Karl-Otto Apel]] both support a postmetaphysical, universal moral theory, but they disagree on the nature and justification of this principle. Habermas disagrees with Apel's view that the principle is a transcendental condition of human activity, while Apel asserts that it is. They each criticize the other's position. Habermas argues that Apel is too concerned with transcendental conditions, while Apel argues that Habermas doesn't value critical discourse enough.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gamwell |first1=Franklin I. |title=Habermas and Apel on communicative ethics: Their difference and the difference it makes |journal=[[Philosophy and Social Criticism]] |date=1997 |volume=23 |issue=2 |pages=21–45 |doi=10.1177/019145379702300202 |s2cid=144776550 |url=https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/019145379702300202}}</ref>


=== Habermas and Rawls ===
=== Habermas and Rawls ===
{{Main|Habermas–Rawls debate}}
{{Main|Habermas–Rawls debate}}
There is a debate between Habermas and [[John Rawls]]. The debate centers around the question of how to do political philosophy under conditions of cultural pluralism, if the aim of political philosophy is to uncover the normative foundation of a modern liberal democracy. Habermas believes that Rawls's view is inconsistent with the idea of popular sovereignty, while Rawls argues that political legitimacy is solely a matter of sound moral reasoning or that democratic will formation has been unduly downgraded in his theory.<ref>Habermas, Jürgen (1995), "Reconciliation Through the Public Use of Reason: Remarks on John Rawls's Political Liberalism", ''Journal of Philosophy'' 92(3): 109-31.</ref><ref>Rawls, John (1995), "Political Liberalism: Reply to Habermas", ''Journal of Philosophy'' 92(3): 132–80</ref>
There is a debate between Habermas and [[John Rawls]]. The debate centers around the question of how to do political philosophy under conditions of cultural pluralism, if the aim of political philosophy is to uncover the normative foundation of a modern liberal democracy. Habermas believes that Rawls's view is inconsistent with the idea of popular sovereignty, while Rawls argues that political legitimacy is solely a matter of sound moral reasoning or that democratic will formation has been unduly downgraded in his theory.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Habermas |first=Jürgen |date=1995 |title=Reconciliation Through the Public Use of Reason: Remarks on John Rawls's Political Liberalism |journal=[[Journal of Philosophy]] |volume=92 |number=3 |pages=109–131}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last=Rawls |first=John |date=1995 |title=Political Liberalism: Reply to Habermas |journal=[[Journal of Philosophy]] |volume=92 |number=3 |pages=132–180}}</ref>


===''Historikerstreit'' (Historians' Quarrel)===
===''Historikerstreit'' (Historians' Quarrel)===
{{Main|Historikerstreit}}
{{Main|Historikerstreit}}
Habermas is famous as a [[public intellectual]] as well as a scholar; most notably, in the 1980s he used the [[popular press]] to attack the German historians [[Ernst Nolte]], [[Michael Stürmer]], [[Klaus Hildebrand]] and [[Andreas Hillgruber]]. Habermas first expressed his views on the above-mentioned historians in the ''[[Die Zeit]]'' on 11 July 1986 in a ''[[feuilleton]]'' (a type of culture and arts opinion essay in German newspapers) entitled "A Kind of Settlement of Damages". Habermas criticized Nolte, Hildebrand, Stürmer and Hillgruber for "apologistic" history writing in regard to the Nazi era, and for seeking to "close Germany's opening to the West" that in Habermas's view had existed since 1945.<ref>Habermas, Jürgen, "A Kind of Settlement of Damages On Apologetic Tendencies In German History Writing", pp. 34–44 from ''Forever In the Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Ernst Piper, Humanities Press, Atlantic Highlands, 1993, p. 43.</ref>
Habermas is famous as a [[public intellectual]] as well as a scholar; most notably, in the 1980s he used the [[popular press]] to attack the German historians [[Ernst Nolte]], [[Michael Stürmer]], [[Klaus Hildebrand]] and [[Andreas Hillgruber]]. Habermas first expressed his views on the above-mentioned historians in the ''[[Die Zeit]]'' on 11 July 1986 in a ''[[feuilleton]]'' (a type of culture and arts opinion essay in German newspapers) entitled "A Kind of Settlement of Damages". Habermas criticized Nolte, Hildebrand, Stürmer and Hillgruber for "apologistic" history writing in regard to the Nazi era, and for seeking to "close Germany's opening to the West" that in Habermas's view had existed since 1945.<ref name="Piper43">{{cite book |last=Habermas |first=Jürgen |chapter=A Kind of Settlement of Damages On Apologetic Tendencies In German History Writing |pages=34–44 [43] |title=Forever In the Shadow of Hitler? |editor1-first=Ernst |editor1-last=Piper |publisher=[[Humanities Press]] |location=Atlantic Highlands |date=1993}}</ref>


Habermas argued that Nolte, Stürmer, Hildebrand and Hillgruber had tried to detach Nazi rule and the [[The Holocaust|Holocaust]] from the mainstream of [[German history]], explain away Nazism as a reaction to [[Bolshevism]], and partially rehabilitate the [[reputation of the Wehrmacht]] (German Army) during [[World War II]]. Habermas wrote that Stürmer was trying to create a "vicarious religion" in German history which, together with the work of Hillgruber, glorifying the last days of the German Army on the Eastern Front, was intended to serve as a "kind of NATO philosophy colored with German nationalism".<ref>Habermas, Jürgen "A Kind of Settlement of Damages" pp. 34–44 from ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), pp. 42–43.</ref> About Hillgruber's statement that [[Adolf Hitler]] wanted to exterminate the Jews "because only such a 'racial revolution' could lend permanence to the world-power status of his ''Reich''", Habermas wrote: "Since Hillgruber does not use the verb in the subjunctive, one does not know whether the historian has adopted the perspective of the particulars this time too".<ref>Habermas, Jürgen "A Kind of Settlement of Damages" pp. 34–44 from ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), pp. 37–38.</ref>
Habermas argued that Nolte, Stürmer, Hildebrand and Hillgruber had tried to detach Nazi rule and the [[The Holocaust|Holocaust]] from the mainstream of [[German history]], explain away Nazism as a reaction to [[Bolshevism]], and partially rehabilitate the [[reputation of the Wehrmacht]] (German Army) during [[World War II]]. Habermas wrote that Stürmer was trying to create a "vicarious religion" in German history which, together with the work of Hillgruber, glorifying the last days of the German Army on the Eastern Front, was intended to serve as a "kind of NATO philosophy colored with German nationalism".<ref>{{cite book |last=Habermas |first=Jürgen |chapter=A Kind of Settlement of Damages On Apologetic Tendencies In German History Writing |pages=34–44 [42–43] |title=Forever In the Shadow of Hitler? |editor1-first=Ernst |editor1-last=Piper |publisher=[[Humanities Press]] |location=Atlantic Highlands |date=1993}}</ref> About Hillgruber's statement that [[Adolf Hitler]] wanted to exterminate the Jews "because only such a 'racial revolution' could lend permanence to the world-power status of his ''Reich''", Habermas wrote: "Since Hillgruber does not use the verb in the subjunctive, one does not know whether the historian has adopted the perspective of the particulars this time too".<ref>{{cite book |last=Habermas |first=Jürgen |chapter=A Kind of Settlement of Damages On Apologetic Tendencies In German History Writing |pages=34–44 [37–38] |title=Forever In the Shadow of Hitler? |editor1-first=Ernst |editor1-last=Piper |publisher=[[Humanities Press]] |location=Atlantic Highlands |date=1993}}</ref>


Habermas wrote: "The unconditional opening of the Federal Republic to the political culture of the West is the greatest intellectual achievement of our postwar period; my generation should be especially proud of this. This event cannot and should not be stabilized by a kind of NATO philosophy colored with German nationalism. The opening of the Federal Republic has been achieved precisely by overcoming the ideology of Central Europe that our revisionists are trying to warm up for us with their geopolitical drumbeat about "the old geographically central position of the Germans in Europe" (Stürmer) and "the reconstruction of the destroyed European Center" (Hillgruber). The only patriotism that will not estrange us from the West is a constitutional patriotism."<ref>Habermas in Piper (1993) p. 43</ref>
Habermas wrote: "The unconditional opening of the Federal Republic to the political culture of the West is the greatest intellectual achievement of our postwar period; my generation should be especially proud of this. This event cannot and should not be stabilized by a kind of NATO philosophy colored with German nationalism. The opening of the Federal Republic has been achieved precisely by overcoming the ideology of Central Europe that our revisionists are trying to warm up for us with their geopolitical drumbeat about "the old geographically central position of the Germans in Europe" (Stürmer) and "the reconstruction of the destroyed European Center" (Hillgruber). The only patriotism that will not estrange us from the West is a constitutional patriotism."<ref name="Piper43"/>


The so-called ''Historikerstreit'' ("Historians' Quarrel") was not at all one-sided, because Habermas was himself attacked by scholars like [[Joachim Fest]],<ref>Fest, Joachim, "Encumbered Remembrance: The Controversy about the Incomparability of National-Socialist Mass Crimes", pp. 63–71 & "Postscript, April 21, 1987", pp. 264–265 from ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), pp. 64–65.</ref> [[Hagen Schulze]],<ref>Schulze, Hagen, "Questions We Have To Face: No Historical Stance without National Identity" pp. 93–97 from ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), p. 94.</ref> Horst Möller,<ref>Möller, Horst, "What May Not Be, Cannot Be: A Plea for Rendering Factual the Controversy about Recent History", pp. 216–221, ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), pp. 216–218.</ref> [[Imanuel Geiss]]<ref>Geiss, Imanuel, "On the ''Historikerstreit''", pp. 254–258 from ''Forever In The Shadow Of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), p. 256.</ref> and Klaus Hildebrand.<ref>Hildebrand, Klaus, "The Age of Tyrants: History and Politics The Administrators of the Enlightenment, the Risk of Scholarship and the Preservation of a Worldview A Reply to Jürgen Habermas", pp. 50–55, & "He Who Wants To Escape the Abyss Will Have Sound It Very Precisely: Is the New German History Writing Revisionist?" pp. 188–195 from ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993).</ref> In turn, Habermas was supported by historians such as [[Martin Broszat]],<ref>Broszat, Martin, "Where the Roads Part: History Is Not A Suitable Substitute for a Religion of Nationalism", pp. 123–129, ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), p. 127.</ref> [[Eberhard Jäckel]],<ref>Jäckel, Eberhard, "The Impoverished Practice of Insinuation: The Singular Aspect of National Socialist Crimes Cannot Be Denied", pp. 74–78 from ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), pp. 74–75.</ref> [[Hans Mommsen]],<ref>Mommsen, Hans, "The New Historical Consciousness and the Relativizing of National Socialism", pp. 114–124 from ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), pp. 114–115.</ref> and [[Hans-Ulrich Wehler]].<ref>Evans, Richard, ''In Hitler's Shadow'', New York: Pantheon Books, 1989, pp. 159–160.</ref>
The so-called ''Historikerstreit'' ("Historians' Quarrel") was not at all one-sided, because Habermas was himself attacked by scholars like [[Joachim Fest]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Fest |first=Joachim |author-link=Joachim Fest |chapter=Encumbered Remembrance: The Controversy about the Incomparability of National-Socialist Mass Crimes |pages=63–71 [64–65] |title=Forever In The Shadow of Hitler? |editor1-last=Piper |editor1-first=Ernst |publisher=[[Humanities Press]] |location=Atlantic Highlands |date=1993}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Fest |first=Joachim |author-link=Joachim Fest |chapter=Postscript, April 21, 1987 |pages=264–265 |title=Forever In The Shadow of Hitler? |editor1-last=Piper |editor1-first=Ernst |publisher=[[Humanities Press]] |location=Atlantic Highlands |date=1993}}</ref> [[Hagen Schulze]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Schulze |first=Hagen |author-link=Hagen Schulze |chapter=Questions We Have To Face: No Historical Stance without National Identity |pages=93–97 [94] |title=Forever In The Shadow of Hitler? |editor1-last=Piper |editor1-first=Ernst |publisher=[[Humanities Press]] |location=Atlantic Highlands |date=1993}}</ref> Horst Möller,<ref>{{cite book |last=Möller |first=Horst |chapter=What May Not Be, Cannot Be: A Plea for Rendering Factual the Controversy about Recent History |pages=216–221 [216–218] |title=Forever In The Shadow of Hitler? |editor1-last=Piper |editor1-first=Ernst |publisher=[[Humanities Press]] |location=Atlantic Highlands |date=1993}}</ref> [[Imanuel Geiss]]<ref>{{cite book |last=Geiss |first=Imanuel |author-link=Imanuel Geiss |chapter=On the ''Historikerstreit'' |pages=254–258 [256] |title=Forever In The Shadow Of Hitler? |editor1-last=Piper |editor1-first=Ernst |publisher=[[Humanities Press]] |location=Atlantic Highlands |date=1993}}</ref> and Klaus Hildebrand.<ref>Hildebrand, Klaus, "The Age of Tyrants: History and Politics The Administrators of the Enlightenment, the Risk of Scholarship and the Preservation of a Worldview A Reply to Jürgen Habermas", pp. 50–55, & "He Who Wants To Escape the Abyss Will Have Sound It Very Precisely: Is the New German History Writing Revisionist?" pp. 188–195 from ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993).</ref> In turn, Habermas was supported by historians such as [[Martin Broszat]],<ref>Broszat, Martin, "Where the Roads Part: History Is Not A Suitable Substitute for a Religion of Nationalism", pp. 123–129, ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), p. 127.</ref> [[Eberhard Jäckel]],<ref>Jäckel, Eberhard, "The Impoverished Practice of Insinuation: The Singular Aspect of National Socialist Crimes Cannot Be Denied", pp. 74–78 from ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), pp. 74–75.</ref> [[Hans Mommsen]],<ref>Mommsen, Hans, "The New Historical Consciousness and the Relativizing of National Socialism", pp. 114–124 from ''Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?'' ed. Piper (1993), pp. 114–115.</ref> and [[Hans-Ulrich Wehler]].<ref>Evans, Richard, ''In Hitler's Shadow'', New York: Pantheon Books, 1989, pp. 159–160.</ref>


===Habermas and Derrida===
===Habermas and Derrida===
Line 162: Line 159:


=== Religious dialogue ===
=== Religious dialogue ===
Habermas's attitudes toward religion have changed throughout the years. Analyst Phillippe Portier identifies three phases in Habermas's attitude towards this social sphere: the first, in the decade of 1980, when the younger Jürgen, in the spirit of Marx, argued against religion seeing it as an "alienating reality" and "control tool"; the second phase, from the mid-1980s to the beginning of the 21st Century, when he stopped discussing it and, as a secular commentator, relegated it to matters of private life; and the third, from then until now, when Habermas saw a positive social role of religion.<ref>Sánchez, Rosalía. 2011. ''[http://www.elmundo.es/elmundo/2011/10/07/cultura/1317980044.html 'San' Jürgen Habermas]''. [[El Mundo (Spain)|El Mundo]]. Access date: 10 January 2015</ref>
Habermas's attitudes toward religion have changed throughout the years. Analyst Phillippe Portier identifies three phases in Habermas's attitude towards this social sphere: the first, in the decade of 1980, when the younger Jürgen, in the spirit of Marx, argued against religion seeing it as an "alienating reality" and "control tool"; the second phase, from the mid-1980s to the beginning of the 21st century, when he stopped discussing it and, as a secular commentator, relegated it to matters of private life; and the third, from then until now, when Habermas saw a positive social role of religion.<ref>Sánchez, Rosalía. 2011. ''[http://www.elmundo.es/elmundo/2011/10/07/cultura/1317980044.html 'San' Jürgen Habermas]''. [[El Mundo (Spain)|El Mundo]]. Access date: 10 January 2015</ref>


In an interview in 1999 Habermas had stated:
In an interview in 1999 Habermas had stated:
Line 188: Line 185:


===Socialist dialogue===
===Socialist dialogue===
Habermas has sided with other 20th-century commentators on Marx such as [[Hannah Arendt]] who have indicated concerns with the limits of totalitarian perspectives often associated with Marx's apparent over-estimation of the emancipatory potential of the forces of production. Arendt had presented this in her book ''[[The Origins of Totalitarianism]]'' and Habermas extends this critique in his writings on functional reductionism in the life-world in his ''[[The Theory of Communicative Action|Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason]]''. As Habermas states:
Habermas has sided with other 20th-century commentators on Marx such as [[Hannah Arendt]] who have indicated concerns with the limits of totalitarian perspectives often associated with Marx's over-estimation of the emancipatory potential of the forces of production. Arendt had presented this in her book ''[[The Origins of Totalitarianism]]'' and Habermas extends this critique in his writings on functional reductionism in the life-world in his ''[[The Theory of Communicative Action|Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason]]''. As Habermas states:


{{blockquote | …traditional Marxist analysis… today, when we use the means of the critique of political economy… can no longer make clear predictions: for that, one would still have to assume the autonomy of a self-reproducing economic system. I do not believe in such an autonomy. Precisely for this reason, the laws governing the economic system are no longer identical to the ones Marx analyzed. Of course, this does not mean that it would be wrong to analyze the mechanism which drives the economic system; but in order for the orthodox version of such an analysis to be valid, the influence of the political system would have to be ignored.<ref name="Habermas, Jurgen 1981" />}}Habermas reiterated the positions that what refuted [[Karl Marx|Marx]] and his theory of [[Class conflict|class struggle]] was the "pacification of class conflict" by the [[welfare state]], which had developed in the West "since 1945", thanks to "a reformist relying on the instruments of [[Keynesian economics]]".<ref>{{Cite book|last=Habermas|first=Jürgen|title=Theory of Communicative Action|publisher=[[Beacon Press]]|year=1987|volume=2|pages=348|translator-last=Thomas|translator-first=McCarthy}}</ref><ref name=":0">{{Cite book|last=Losurdo|first=Domenico|title=Class Struggle|publisher=[[Palgrave Macmillan]]|year=2016|isbn=978-1-137-52387-7|location=|pages=3|doi=10.1057/978-1-349-70660-0|lccn=2016940579}}</ref> Italian philosopher and historian [[Domenico Losurdo]] criticised the main point of these claims as "marked by the absence of a question that should be obvious:— Was the advent of the welfare state the inevitable result of a tendency inherent in [[capitalism]]? Or was it the result of political and social mobilization by the subaltern classes—in the final analysis, of a class struggle? Had the German philosopher posed this question, perhaps he would have avoided assuming the permanence of the welfare state, whose precariousness and progressive dismantlement are now obvious to everyone".<ref name=":0" />
{{blockquote | …traditional Marxist analysis… today, when we use the means of the critique of political economy… can no longer make clear predictions: for that, one would still have to assume the autonomy of a self-reproducing economic system. I do not believe in such an autonomy. Precisely for this reason, the laws governing the economic system are no longer identical to the ones Marx analyzed. Of course, this does not mean that it would be wrong to analyze the mechanism which drives the economic system; but in order for the orthodox version of such an analysis to be valid, the influence of the political system would have to be ignored.<ref name="Habermas, Jurgen 1981" />}}Habermas reiterated the positions that what refuted [[Karl Marx|Marx]] and his theory of [[Class conflict|class struggle]] was the "pacification of class conflict" by the [[welfare state]], which had developed in the West "since 1945", thanks to "a reformist relying on the instruments of [[Keynesian economics]]".<ref>{{Cite book|last=Habermas|first=Jürgen|title=Theory of Communicative Action|publisher=[[Beacon Press]]|year=1987|volume=2|pages=348|translator-last=Thomas|translator-first=McCarthy}}</ref><ref name=":0">{{Cite book|last=Losurdo|first=Domenico|title=Class Struggle|publisher=[[Palgrave Macmillan]]|year=2016|isbn=978-1-137-52387-7|pages=3|doi=10.1057/978-1-349-70660-0|s2cid=265035687 |lccn=2016940579}}</ref> Italian philosopher and historian [[Domenico Losurdo]] criticised the main point of these claims as "marked by the absence of a question that should be obvious:— Was the advent of the welfare state the inevitable result of a tendency inherent in [[capitalism]]? Or was it the result of political and social mobilization by the subaltern classes—in the final analysis, of a class struggle? Had the German philosopher posed this question, perhaps he would have avoided assuming the permanence of the welfare state, whose precariousness and progressive dismantlement are now obvious to everyone".<ref name=":0" />


=== Controversy about wars ===
=== Controversy about wars ===
In 1999, Habermas addressed the [[Kosovo War]]. Habermas defended [[NATO bombing of Yugoslavia|NATO's intervention]] in an article for ''Die Zeit'', which stirred controversy.<ref>Jürgen Habermas, 'Bestialitiit und Humanitiit: Ein Krieg an der Grenze zwischen Recht und Moral', ''Die Zeit'', 29 April 1999; in English as 'Bestiality and Humanity: A War on the Border between Law and Morality', in William Buckley (ed.), ''Kosovo: Contending Voices on the Balkan Intervention'' (2000).</ref>
In 1999, Habermas addressed the [[Kosovo War]]. Habermas defended [[NATO bombing of Yugoslavia|NATO's intervention]] in an article for ''Die Zeit'', which stirred controversy.<ref>Jürgen Habermas, 'Bestialität und Humanität: Ein Krieg an der Grenze zwischen Recht und Moral', ''Die Zeit'', 29 April 1999; in English as 'Bestiality and Humanity: A War on the Border between Law and Morality', in William Buckley (ed.), ''Kosovo: Contending Voices on the Balkan Intervention'' (2000).</ref>


In 2001, Habermas argued that the United States should not go to war in [[Iraq War|Iraq]].<ref>Jürgen Habermas, "Letter to America", ''[[The Nation]]'', 16 December 2002</ref>
In 2001, Habermas argued that the United States should not go to war in [[Iraq War|Iraq]].<ref>Jürgen Habermas, "Letter to America", ''[[The Nation]]'', 16 December 2002</ref>


=== European Union ===
=== European Union ===
During the [[European debt crisis]], Habermas criticized [[Angela Merkel]]'s leadership in Europe, In 2013, Habermas clashed with [[Wolfgang Streeck]], who argued the kind of European federalism espoused by Habermas as the root of the continent's crisis.<ref>Philip Oltermann, "Merkel 'gambling away' Germany's reputation over Greece, says Habermas", ''The Guardian'' (16 July 2015)</ref>
During the [[European debt crisis]], Habermas criticized [[Angela Merkel]]'s leadership in Europe. In 2013, Habermas clashed with [[Wolfgang Streeck]], who argued the kind of European federalism espoused by Habermas as the root of the continent's crisis.<ref>Philip Oltermann, "Merkel 'gambling away' Germany's reputation over Greece, says Habermas", ''The Guardian'' (16 July 2015)</ref>


==Awards==
==Awards==
Line 223: Line 220:
* 2013: [[Erasmus Prize]]<ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.knaw.nl/nl/actueel/agenda/the-future-of-democracy-with-jurgen-habermas |title=The future of democracy, with Jürgen Habermas |publisher=KNAW |access-date=6 November 2013}}</ref>
* 2013: [[Erasmus Prize]]<ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.knaw.nl/nl/actueel/agenda/the-future-of-democracy-with-jurgen-habermas |title=The future of democracy, with Jürgen Habermas |publisher=KNAW |access-date=6 November 2013}}</ref>
* 2015: [[Kluge Prize]]
* 2015: [[Kluge Prize]]
* 2021: [[Sheikh Zayed Book Award]] (declined, citing the UAE's political system as a repressive non-democracy)<ref>{{Cite web|title=German philosopher Habermas rejects UAE's Zayed Book Award|url=https://apnews.com/article/europe-middle-east-entertainment-government-and-politics-arts-and-entertainment-1fe05291c8fd37bb106d6ee8423182cf|access-date=2021-05-02|website=AP NEWS|date=2 May 2021}}</ref><ref>{{Cite news|last=SPIEGEL|first=Dietmar Pieper, DER|title=Jürgen Habermas und die emiratische Propaganda: Lässt sich der Starphilosoph vereinnahmen?|url=https://www.spiegel.de/politik/ausland/juergen-habermas-und-die-emiratische-propaganda-laesst-sich-der-star-philosoph-vereinnahmen-a-adfdc2f3-4ffa-4217-bb0e-c5bfd3b1aac8|access-date=2021-05-02|newspaper=Der Spiegel|date=2 May 2021|language=de}}</ref><ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.dw.com/en/j%C3%BCrgen-habermas-turns-down-uae-award-over-human-rights-concerns/a-57405254 |title=Jürgen Habermas turns down UAE award over human rights concerns |website=DW |date=2 May 2021 }}</ref>
* 2021: [[Sheikh Zayed Book Award]] (declined, citing the UAE's political system as a repressive non-democracy)<ref>{{Cite web|title=German philosopher Habermas rejects UAE's Zayed Book Award|url=https://apnews.com/article/europe-middle-east-entertainment-government-and-politics-arts-and-entertainment-1fe05291c8fd37bb106d6ee8423182cf|access-date=2 May 2021|website=AP NEWS|date=2 May 2021}}</ref><ref>{{Cite news|last=SPIEGEL|first=Dietmar Pieper, DER|title=Jürgen Habermas und die emiratische Propaganda: Lässt sich der Starphilosoph vereinnahmen?|url=https://www.spiegel.de/politik/ausland/juergen-habermas-und-die-emiratische-propaganda-laesst-sich-der-star-philosoph-vereinnahmen-a-adfdc2f3-4ffa-4217-bb0e-c5bfd3b1aac8|access-date=2 May 2021|newspaper=Der Spiegel|date=2 May 2021|language=de}}</ref><ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.dw.com/en/j%C3%BCrgen-habermas-turns-down-uae-award-over-human-rights-concerns/a-57405254 |title=Jürgen Habermas turns down UAE award over human rights concerns |website=DW |date=2 May 2021 }}</ref>
* 2022: [[Dialectic Medal]]<ref>"Jürgen Habermas Awarded Inaugural Dialectic Medal" https://www.dialecticinstitute.org/medal/habermas.htm</ref>
* 2022: [[Dialectic Medal]]<ref>"Jürgen Habermas Awarded Inaugural Dialectic Medal" https://www.dialecticinstitute.org/medal/habermas.htm</ref>
* 2022 [[Pour le Mérite]]<ref name="ORDEN POUR LE MÉRITE">{{cite web | title=Habermas | website=ORDEN POUR LE MÉRITE | url=https://www.orden-pourlemerite.de/mitglieder/juergen-habermas | language=de | access-date=11 June 2023}}</ref>
* 2022 [[Pour le Mérite]]<ref name="ORDEN POUR LE MÉRITE">{{cite web | title=Habermas | website=ORDEN POUR LE MÉRITE | url=https://www.orden-pourlemerite.de/mitglieder/juergen-habermas | language=de | access-date=11 June 2023}}</ref>
Line 263: Line 260:
* ''The Crisis of the European Union'' (2012)
* ''The Crisis of the European Union'' (2012)
* ''This Too a History of Philosophy'' (2019)
* ''This Too a History of Philosophy'' (2019)
* ''A New Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere and Deliberative Politics'' (2023)
{{div col end}}
{{div col end}}


Line 291: Line 289:
* Erik Oddvar Eriksen and Jarle Weigard, ''Understanding Habermas: Communicative Action and Deliberative Democracy'', Continuum International Publishing, 2004 ({{ISBN|0-8264-7179-X}}).
* Erik Oddvar Eriksen and Jarle Weigard, ''Understanding Habermas: Communicative Action and Deliberative Democracy'', Continuum International Publishing, 2004 ({{ISBN|0-8264-7179-X}}).
: {{smaller|A recent and comprehensive introduction to Habermas's mature theory and its political implications both national and global.}}
: {{smaller|A recent and comprehensive introduction to Habermas's mature theory and its political implications both national and global.}}
* Alexandre Guilherme and W.John Morgan,'Habermas(1929-)-dialogue as communicative rationality', Chapter 9 in ''Philosophy, Dialogue, and Education: Nine modern European philosophers'', Routledge, London and New York, pp.&nbsp;140– 154. {{ISBN|978-1-138-83149-0}}.
* Alexandre Guilherme and W.John Morgan,'Habermas(1929–)-dialogue as communicative rationality', Chapter 9 in ''Philosophy, Dialogue, and Education: Nine modern European philosophers'', Routledge, London and New York, pp.&nbsp;140– 154. {{ISBN|978-1-138-83149-0}}.
* Detlef Horster. ''Habermas: An Introduction''. Pennbridge, 1992 ({{ISBN|1-880055-01-5}})
* Detlef Horster. ''Habermas: An Introduction''. Pennbridge, 1992 ({{ISBN|1-880055-01-5}})
* [[Martin Jay]], ''Marxism and Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from Lukacs to Habermas'' (Chapter 9), University of California Press, 1986. ({{ISBN|0-520-05742-2}})
* [[Martin Jay]], ''Marxism and Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from Lukacs to Habermas'' (Chapter 9), University of California Press, 1986. ({{ISBN|0-520-05742-2}})
Line 301: Line 299:
* ''Moderne Religion? Theologische und religionsphilosophische Reaktionen auf Jürgen Habermas''. Hrsg. v. Knut Wenzel und Thomas M. Schmidt. Freiburg, Herder, 2009.
* ''Moderne Religion? Theologische und religionsphilosophische Reaktionen auf Jürgen Habermas''. Hrsg. v. Knut Wenzel und Thomas M. Schmidt. Freiburg, Herder, 2009.
* Luca Corchia, ''[https://books.google.com/books?id=-T14AQAAQBAJ Jürgen Habermas. A bibliography: works and studies (1952–2013): With an Introduction by Stefan Müller-Doohm]'', Arnus Edizioni – Il Campano, Pisa, 2013.
* Luca Corchia, ''[https://books.google.com/books?id=-T14AQAAQBAJ Jürgen Habermas. A bibliography: works and studies (1952–2013): With an Introduction by Stefan Müller-Doohm]'', Arnus Edizioni – Il Campano, Pisa, 2013.
*{{cite book |last=Corchia |first=Luca |title=Jürgen Habermas. A Bibliography. 1. Works of Jürgen Habermas (1952–2018)|date=April 2018 |publisher=Department of Political Science, University of Pisa (Italy), 156 pp |url=https://www.academia.edu/38973021}}.
* {{cite book |last=Corchia |first=Luca |title=Jürgen Habermas. A Bibliography. 1. Works of Jürgen Habermas (1952–2018) |date=April 2018 |publisher=Department of Political Science, University of Pisa (Italy), 156 pp |url=https://www.academia.edu/38973021}}.
*{{cite book |last=Corchia |first=Luca |title=Jürgen Habermas. A bibliography. 2. Studies on Jürgen Habermas (1962–2015) |date=February 2016 |publisher=Department of Political Science, University of Pisa (Italy), 468 pp |url=https://www.academia.edu/22537303}}.
* {{cite book |last=Corchia |first=Luca |title=Jürgen Habermas. A bibliography. 2. Studies on Jürgen Habermas (1962–2015) |date=February 2016 |publisher=Department of Political Science, University of Pisa (Italy), 468 pp |url=https://www.academia.edu/22537303}}.
*Peter Koller, Christian Hiebaum, ''Jürgen Habermas: Faktizität und Geltung'', Walter de Gruyter 2016.
* Peter Koller, Christian Hiebaum, ''Jürgen Habermas: Faktizität und Geltung'', [[Walter de Gruyter]], 2016.


==External links==
==External links==
{{sister project links|d=Q76357|c=Category:Jürgen Habermas|n=no|b=no|v=no|voy=no|s=no|wikt=no|m=no|mw=no|species=no}}
{{sister project links|d=Q76357|c=Category:Jürgen Habermas|n=no|b=no|v=no|voy=no|s=no|wikt=no|m=no|mw=no|species=no}}
* {{Sep entry|habermas|Jürgen Habermas|James Gordon Finlayson, Dafydd Huw Rees}}
* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/habermas/ Extensive article] in the [[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/habermas/ Extensive article] in the [[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/habermas/ Extensive article] in the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
* [http://www.habermasforum.dk/ Habermas Forum] by Thomas Gregersen; updated bibliography, news and literature on Habermas
* [http://www.habermasforum.dk/ Habermas Forum] by Thomas Gregersen; updated bibliography, news and literature on Habermas
* [http://www.signandsight.com/features/676.html ''Towards a United States of Europe''], by Jürgen Habermas, at signandsight.com, published 27 March 2006
* [http://www.signandsight.com/features/676.html ''Towards a United States of Europe''], by Jürgen Habermas, at signandsight.com, published 27 March 2006
Line 350: Line 348:
{{philosophy of science}}
{{philosophy of science}}
{{Social and political philosophy}}
{{Social and political philosophy}}
{{Political philosophy}}
{{Jurisprudence}}
{{Jurisprudence}}
{{Critical theory}}
{{Critical theory}}
Line 366: Line 365:
[[Category:Communication theorists]]
[[Category:Communication theorists]]
[[Category:Critical theorists]]
[[Category:Critical theorists]]
[[Category:Philosophers of science]]
[[Category:German philosophers of science]]
[[Category:Philosophers of technology]]
[[Category:German philosophers of technology]]
[[Category:Fellows of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences]]
[[Category:Fellows of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences]]
[[Category:Fellows of the British Academy]]
[[Category:Fellows of the British Academy]]
Line 388: Line 387:
[[Category:People from Düsseldorf]]
[[Category:People from Düsseldorf]]
[[Category:People from the Rhine Province]]
[[Category:People from the Rhine Province]]
[[Category:Philosophers of language]]
[[Category:German philosophers of language]]
[[Category:Pragmatists]]
[[Category:Pragmatists]]
[[Category:Rhetoricians]]
[[Category:Rhetoricians]]
Line 397: Line 396:
[[Category:University of Marburg alumni]]
[[Category:University of Marburg alumni]]
[[Category:Academic staff of the University of Marburg]]
[[Category:Academic staff of the University of Marburg]]
[[Category:Epistemologists]]
[[Category:German epistemologists]]
[[Category:Philosophers of social science]]
[[Category:Philosophers of social science]]
[[Category:Holberg Prize laureates]]
[[Category:Holberg Prize laureates]]

Revision as of 11:30, 12 April 2024

Jürgen Habermas
Habermas in 2014
Born
Jürgen Habermas

(1929-06-18) 18 June 1929 (age 94)
EducationUniversity of Bonn (PhD)
University of Marburg (Dr. phil. hab.)
Spouse
Ute Wesselhöft
(m. 1955)
Children
  • Tilmann (b. 1956)
  • Rebekka (1959–2023)
  • Judith (b. 1967)
EraContemporary philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
Main interests
Notable ideas
Signature

Jürgen Habermas (UK: /ˈhɑːbərmæs/, US: /-mɑːs/;[3] German: [ˈjʏʁɡn̩ ˈhaːbɐmaːs] ;[4][5] born 18 June 1929) is a German philosopher and social theorist in the tradition of critical theory and pragmatism. His work addresses communicative rationality and the public sphere.

Associated with the Frankfurt School, Habermas's work focuses on the foundations of epistemology and social theory, the analysis of advanced capitalism and democracy, the rule of law in a critical social-evolutionary context, albeit within the confines of the natural law tradition,[6] and contemporary politics, particularly German politics. Habermas's theoretical system is devoted to revealing the possibility of reason, emancipation, and rational-critical communication latent in modern institutions and in the human capacity to deliberate and pursue rational interests. Habermas is known for his work on the concept of modernity, particularly with respect to the discussions of rationalization originally set forth by Max Weber. He has been influenced by American pragmatism, action theory, and poststructuralism.

Biography

Habermas was born in Düsseldorf, Rhine Province, in 1929.[7] He was born with a cleft palate and had corrective surgery twice during childhood.[8] Habermas argues that his speech disability made him think differently about the importance of deep dependence and of communication.[9] He grew up in Gummersbach.

As a young teenager, he was profoundly affected by World War II. Until his graduation from grammar school, Habermas lived in Gummersbach, near Cologne. His father, Ernst Habermas, was executive director of the Cologne Chamber of Industry and Commerce, and was described by Habermas as a Nazi sympathizer and, from 1933, a member of the Nazi Party NSDAP. Habermas himself was a Jungvolkführer, a leader of the German Jungvolk, which was a section of the Hitler Youth. He was brought up in a staunchly Protestant milieu, his grandfather being the director of the seminary in Gummersbach. He studied at the universities of Göttingen (1949/50), Zurich (1950/51), and Bonn (1951–54) and earned a doctorate in philosophy from Bonn in 1954 with a dissertation written on the conflict between "the Absolute" and history in Schelling's thought, entitled, Das Absolute und die Geschichte. Von der Zwiespältigkeit in Schellings Denken ("The Absolute and History: On the Schism in Schelling's Thought").[10] His dissertation committee included Erich Rothacker and Oskar Becker.[10]

From 1956 on, he studied philosophy and sociology under the critical theorists Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno at the Goethe University Frankfurt's Institute for Social Research, but because of a rift between the two over his dissertation—Horkheimer had made unacceptable demands for revision—as well as his own belief that the Frankfurt School had become paralyzed with political skepticism and disdain for modern culture,[11] he finished his habilitation in political science at the University of Marburg under the Marxist Wolfgang Abendroth. His habilitation work was entitled Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit. Untersuchungen zu einer Kategorie der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft (published in English translation in 1989 as The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society). It is a detailed social history of the development of the bourgeois public sphere from its origins in the 18th century salons up to its transformation through the influence of capital-driven mass media. In 1961 he became a Privatdozent in Marburg, and—in a move that was highly unusual for the German academic scene of that time—he was offered the position of "extraordinary professor" (professor without chair) of philosophy at the University of Heidelberg (at the instigation of Hans-Georg Gadamer and Karl Löwith) in 1962, which he accepted. In this same year he gained his first serious public attention, in Germany, with the publication of his habilitation. In 1964, strongly supported by Adorno, Habermas returned to Frankfurt to take over Horkheimer's chair in philosophy and sociology. The philosopher Albrecht Wellmer was his assistant in Frankfurt from 1966 to 1970.

He accepted the position of Director of the Max Planck Institute for the Study of the Scientific-Technical World in Starnberg (near Munich) in 1971, and worked there until 1983, two years after the publication of his magnum opus, The Theory of Communicative Action. He was elected a Foreign Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in 1984.[12]

Habermas then returned to his chair at Frankfurt and the directorship of the Institute for Social Research. Since retiring from Frankfurt in 1993, Habermas has continued to publish extensively. In 1986, he received the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Prize of the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft, which is the highest honour awarded in German research. He also holds the position of "permanent visiting" professor at Northwestern University in Evanston, Illinois, and "Theodor Heuss Professor" at The New School, New York.

Habermas was awarded the Prince of Asturias Award in Social Sciences of 2003. Habermas was also the 2004 Kyoto Laureate[13] in the Arts and Philosophy section. He traveled to San Diego and on 5 March 2005, as part of the University of San Diego's Kyoto Symposium, gave a speech entitled The Public Role of Religion in Secular Context, regarding the evolution of separation of church and state from neutrality to intense secularism. He received the 2005 Holberg International Memorial Prize (about €520,000). In 2007, Habermas was listed as the seventh most-cited author in the humanities (including the social sciences) by The Times Higher Education Guide, ahead of Max Weber and behind Erving Goffman.[14] Bibliometric studies demonstrate his continuing influence and increasing relevance.[15]

Jürgen Habermas was the father of Rebekka Habermas (1959–2023), historian of German social and cultural history and professor of modern history at the University of Göttingen.

Teacher and mentor

Habermas was a famed teacher and mentor. Among his most prominent students were the pragmatic philosopher Herbert Schnädelbach (theorist of discourse distinction and rationality), the political sociologist Claus Offe (professor at the Hertie School of Governance in Berlin), the social philosopher Johann Arnason (professor at La Trobe University and chief editor of the journal Thesis Eleven), the social philosopher Hans-Herbert Kögler (Chair of Philosophy at the University of North Florida), the sociological theorist Hans Joas (professor at the University of Erfurt and at the University of Chicago), the theorist of societal evolution Klaus Eder, the social philosopher Axel Honneth, the political theorist David Rasmussen (professor at Boston College and chief editor of the journal Philosophy & Social Criticism), the environmental ethicist Konrad Ott, the anarcho-capitalist philosopher Hans-Hermann Hoppe (who came to reject much of Habermas's thought),[16] the American philosopher Thomas McCarthy, the co-creator of mindful inquiry in social research Jeremy J. Shapiro, the political philosopher Cristina Lafont (Harold H. and Virginia Anderson Professor of Philosophy at Northwestern University), and the assassinated Serbian prime minister Zoran Đinđić.

Philosophy and social theory

Habermas has constructed a comprehensive framework of philosophy and social theory drawing on a number of intellectual traditions:[17]

Jürgen Habermas considers his major contribution to be the development of the concept and theory of communicative reason or communicative rationality, which distinguishes itself from the rationalist tradition, by locating rationality in structures of interpersonal linguistic communication rather than in the structure of the cosmos. This social theory advances the goals of human emancipation, while maintaining an inclusive universalist moral framework. This framework rests on the argument called universal pragmatics—that all speech acts have an inherent telos (the Greek word for "purpose")—the goal of mutual understanding, and that human beings possess the communicative competence to bring about such understanding. Habermas built the framework out of the speech-act philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein, J. L. Austin and John Searle, the sociological theory of the interactional constitution of mind and self of George Herbert Mead, the theories of moral development of Jean Piaget and Lawrence Kohlberg, and the discourse ethics of his Frankfurt colleague and fellow student Karl-Otto Apel.

Habermas's works resonate within the traditions of Kant and the Enlightenment and of democratic socialism through his emphasis on the potential for transforming the world and arriving at a more humane, just, and egalitarian society through the realization of the human potential for reason, in part through discourse ethics. While Habermas has stated that the Enlightenment is an "unfinished project," he argues it should be corrected and complemented, not discarded.[19] In this he distances himself from the Frankfurt School, criticizing it, as well as much of postmodernist thought, for excessive pessimism, radicalism, and exaggerations.[19]

Within sociology, Habermas's major contribution was the development of a comprehensive theory of societal evolution and modernization focusing on the difference between communicative rationality and rationalization on one hand and strategic/instrumental rationality and rationalization on the other. This includes a critique from a communicative standpoint of the differentiation-based theory of social systems developed by Niklas Luhmann, a student of Talcott Parsons.

His defence of modernity and civil society has been a source of inspiration to others, and is considered a major philosophical alternative to the varieties of poststructuralism. He has also offered an influential analysis of late capitalism.

Habermas perceives the rationalization, humanization and democratization of society in terms of the institutionalization of the potential for rationality that is inherent in the communicative competence that is unique to the human species. Habermas contends that communicative competence has developed through the course of evolution, but in contemporary society it is often suppressed or weakened by the way in which major domains of social life, such as the market, the state, and organizations, have been given over to or taken over by strategic/instrumental rationality, so that the logic of the system supplants that of the lifeworld.

Reconstructive science

Habermas introduces the concept of "reconstructive science" with a double purpose: to place the "general theory of society" between philosophy and social science and re-establish the rift between the "great theorization" and the "empirical research". The model of "rational reconstructions" represents the main thread of the surveys about the "structures" of the world of life ("culture", "society" and "personality") and their respective "functions" (cultural reproductions, social integrations and socialization). For this purpose, the dialectics between "symbolic representation" of "the structures subordinated to all worlds of life" ("internal relationships") and the "material reproduction" of the social systems in their complex ("external relationships" between social systems and environment) has to be considered.

This model finds an application, above all, in the "theory of the social evolution", starting from the reconstruction of the necessary conditions for a phylogeny of the socio-cultural life forms (the "hominization") until an analysis of the development of "social formations", which Habermas subdivides into primitive, traditional, modern and contemporary formations. "This paper is an attempt, primarily, to formalize the model of "reconstruction of the logic of development" of "social formations" summed up by Habermas through the differentiation between vital world and social systems (and, within them, through the "rationalization of the world of life" and the "growth in complexity of the social systems"). Secondly, it tries to offer some methodological clarifications about the "explanation of the dynamics" of "historical processes" and, in particular, about the "theoretical meaning" of the evolutional theory's propositions. Even if the German sociologist considers that the "ex-post rational reconstructions" and "the models system/environment" cannot have a complete "historiographical application", these certainly act as a general premise in the argumentative structure of the "historical explanation".[20]

The public sphere

In The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere, Habermas argues that prior to the 18th century, European culture had been dominated by a "representational" culture, where one party sought to "represent" itself on its audience by overwhelming its subjects.[21] As an example of "representational" culture, Habermas argued that Louis XIV's Palace of Versailles was meant to show the greatness of the French state and its King by overpowering the senses of visitors to the Palace.[21] Habermas identifies "representational" culture as corresponding to the feudal stage of development according to Marxist theory, arguing that the coming of the capitalist stage of development marked the appearance of Öffentlichkeit (the public sphere).[22] In the culture characterized by Öffentlichkeit, there occurred a public space outside of the control by the state, where individuals exchanged views and knowledge.[23]

In Habermas's view, the growth in newspapers, journals, reading clubs, Masonic lodges, and coffeehouses in 18th-century Europe, all in different ways, marked the gradual replacement of "representational" culture with Öffentlichkeit culture.[23] Habermas argued that the essential characteristic of the Öffentlichkeit culture was its "critical" nature.[23] Unlike "representational" culture where only one party was active and the other passive, the Öffentlichkeit culture was characterized by a dialogue as individuals either met in conversation, or exchanged views via the print media.[23] Habermas maintains that as Britain was the most liberal country in Europe, the culture of the public sphere emerged there first around 1700, and the growth of Öffentlichkeit culture took place over most of the 18th century in Continental Europe.[23] In his view, the French Revolution was in large part caused by the collapse of "representational" culture, and its replacement by Öffentlichkeit culture.[23] Though Habermas's main concern in The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere was to expose what he regarded as the deceptive nature of free institutions in the West, his book had a major effect on the historiography of the French Revolution.[22]

According to Habermas, a variety of factors resulted in the eventual decay of the public sphere, including the growth of a commercial mass media, which turned the critical public into a passive consumer public; and the welfare state, which merged the state with society so thoroughly that the public sphere was squeezed out. It also turned the "public sphere" into a site of self-interested contestation for the resources of the state rather than a space for the development of a public-minded rational consensus.

His most known work to date, the Theory of Communicative Action (1981), is based on an adaptation of Talcott Parsons AGIL Paradigm. In this work, Habermas voiced criticism of the process of modernization, which he saw as inflexible direction forced through by economic and administrative rationalization.[24] Habermas outlined how our everyday lives are penetrated by formal systems as parallel to development of the welfare state, corporate capitalism and mass consumption.[24] These reinforcing trends rationalize public life.[24] Disfranchisement of citizens occurs as political parties and interest groups become rationalized and representative democracy replaces participatory one.[24] In consequence, boundaries between public and private, the individual and society, the system and the lifeworld are deteriorating.[24] Democratic public life cannot develop where matters of public importance are not discussed by citizens.[25] An "ideal speech situation"[26] requires participants to have the same capacities of discourse, social equality and their words are not confused by ideology or other errors.[25] In this version of the consensus theory of truth Habermas maintains that truth is what would be agreed upon in an ideal speech situation.

Habermas has expressed optimism about the possibility of the revival of the public sphere.[27] He discerns a hope for the future where the representative democracy-reliant nation-state is replaced by a deliberative democracy-reliant political organism based on the equal rights and obligations of citizens.[27] In such a direct democracy-driven system, the activist public sphere is needed for debates on matters of public importance as well as the mechanism for that discussion to affect the decision-making process.

Habermas versus postmodernists

Habermas offered some early criticisms in an essay, "Modernity versus Postmodernity" (1981),[28] which has achieved wide recognition. In that essay, Habermas raises the issue of whether, in light of the failures of the twentieth century, we "should try to hold on to the intentions of the Enlightenment, feeble as they may be, or should we declare the entire project of modernity a lost cause?"[29] Habermas refuses to give up on the possibility of a rational, "scientific" understanding of the life-world.

Habermas has several main criticisms of postmodernism:

  1. Postmodernists are equivocal about whether they are producing serious theory or literature;
  2. Postmodernists are animated by normative sentiments, but the nature of those sentiments remains concealed from the reader;
  3. Postmodernism has a totalizing perspective that fails "to differentiate phenomena and practices that occur within modern society";[29]
  4. Postmodernists ignore everyday life and its practices, which Habermas finds absolutely central.

Key dialogues and engagement with politics

Positivism dispute

The positivism dispute was a political-philosophical dispute between the critical rationalists (Karl Popper, Hans Albert) and the Frankfurt School (Theodor Adorno, Jürgen Habermas) in 1961, about the methodology of the social sciences. It grew into a broad discussion within German sociology from 1961 to 1969.

Habermas and Gadamer

There is a controversy between Habermas and Hans-Georg Gadamer about limits of hermeneutics. Gadamer completed his magnum opus, Truth and Method, in 1960, and engaged in his debate with Habermas over the possibility of transcending history and culture in order to find a truly objective position from which to critique society.

During the 1960s, Gadamer supported Habermas and advocated for him to be offered a job at Heidelberg before he had completed his Habilitation, despite Max Horkheimer's objections. While they both criticized positivism, a philosophical disagreement arose between them in the 1970s. This disagreement expanded the scope of Gadamer's philosophical influence. Despite fundamental agreements between them, such as starting from the hermeneutic tradition and returning to Greek practical philosophy, Habermas argued that Gadamer's emphasis on tradition and prejudice blinded him to the ideological operation of power. Habermas believed that Gadamer's approach failed to enable critical reflection on the sources of ideology in society. He accused Gadamer of endorsing a dogmatic stance toward tradition, which made it difficult to identify distortions in understanding. Gadamer countered that refusing the universal nature of hermeneutics was the more dogmatic stance because it affirmed the deception that the subject can free itself from the past.[30]

Habermas and Foucault

There is a dispute concerning whether Michel Foucault's ideas of "power analytics" and "genealogy" or Jürgen Habermas's ideas of "communicative rationality" and "discourse ethics" provide a better critique of the nature of power in society. The debate compares and evaluates the central ideas of Habermas and Foucault as they pertain to questions of power, reason, ethics, modernity, democracy, civil society, and social action.

Habermas and Luhmann

Niklas Luhmann proposed that society could be successfully analyzed through systems theory. There is a conflict between Jürgen Habermas's theory of communicative action and Luhmann's systems theory.

Habermas and Apel

Habermas and Karl-Otto Apel both support a postmetaphysical, universal moral theory, but they disagree on the nature and justification of this principle. Habermas disagrees with Apel's view that the principle is a transcendental condition of human activity, while Apel asserts that it is. They each criticize the other's position. Habermas argues that Apel is too concerned with transcendental conditions, while Apel argues that Habermas doesn't value critical discourse enough.[31]

Habermas and Rawls

There is a debate between Habermas and John Rawls. The debate centers around the question of how to do political philosophy under conditions of cultural pluralism, if the aim of political philosophy is to uncover the normative foundation of a modern liberal democracy. Habermas believes that Rawls's view is inconsistent with the idea of popular sovereignty, while Rawls argues that political legitimacy is solely a matter of sound moral reasoning or that democratic will formation has been unduly downgraded in his theory.[32][33]

Historikerstreit (Historians' Quarrel)

Habermas is famous as a public intellectual as well as a scholar; most notably, in the 1980s he used the popular press to attack the German historians Ernst Nolte, Michael Stürmer, Klaus Hildebrand and Andreas Hillgruber. Habermas first expressed his views on the above-mentioned historians in the Die Zeit on 11 July 1986 in a feuilleton (a type of culture and arts opinion essay in German newspapers) entitled "A Kind of Settlement of Damages". Habermas criticized Nolte, Hildebrand, Stürmer and Hillgruber for "apologistic" history writing in regard to the Nazi era, and for seeking to "close Germany's opening to the West" that in Habermas's view had existed since 1945.[34]

Habermas argued that Nolte, Stürmer, Hildebrand and Hillgruber had tried to detach Nazi rule and the Holocaust from the mainstream of German history, explain away Nazism as a reaction to Bolshevism, and partially rehabilitate the reputation of the Wehrmacht (German Army) during World War II. Habermas wrote that Stürmer was trying to create a "vicarious religion" in German history which, together with the work of Hillgruber, glorifying the last days of the German Army on the Eastern Front, was intended to serve as a "kind of NATO philosophy colored with German nationalism".[35] About Hillgruber's statement that Adolf Hitler wanted to exterminate the Jews "because only such a 'racial revolution' could lend permanence to the world-power status of his Reich", Habermas wrote: "Since Hillgruber does not use the verb in the subjunctive, one does not know whether the historian has adopted the perspective of the particulars this time too".[36]

Habermas wrote: "The unconditional opening of the Federal Republic to the political culture of the West is the greatest intellectual achievement of our postwar period; my generation should be especially proud of this. This event cannot and should not be stabilized by a kind of NATO philosophy colored with German nationalism. The opening of the Federal Republic has been achieved precisely by overcoming the ideology of Central Europe that our revisionists are trying to warm up for us with their geopolitical drumbeat about "the old geographically central position of the Germans in Europe" (Stürmer) and "the reconstruction of the destroyed European Center" (Hillgruber). The only patriotism that will not estrange us from the West is a constitutional patriotism."[34]

The so-called Historikerstreit ("Historians' Quarrel") was not at all one-sided, because Habermas was himself attacked by scholars like Joachim Fest,[37][38] Hagen Schulze,[39] Horst Möller,[40] Imanuel Geiss[41] and Klaus Hildebrand.[42] In turn, Habermas was supported by historians such as Martin Broszat,[43] Eberhard Jäckel,[44] Hans Mommsen,[45] and Hans-Ulrich Wehler.[46]

Habermas and Derrida

Habermas and Jacques Derrida engaged in a series of disputes beginning in the 1980s and culminating in a mutual understanding and friendship in the late 1990s that lasted until Derrida's death in 2004.[47] They originally came in contact when Habermas invited Derrida to speak at The University of Frankfurt in 1984. The next year Habermas published "Beyond a Temporalized Philosophy of Origins: Derrida" in The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity in which he described Derrida's method as being unable to provide a foundation for social critique.[48] Derrida, citing Habermas as an example, remarked that, "those who have accused me of reducing philosophy to literature or logic to rhetoric ... have visibly and carefully avoided reading me".[49] After Derrida's final rebuttal in 1989 the two philosophers did not continue, but, as Derrida described it, groups in the academy "conducted a kind of 'war', in which we ourselves never took part, either personally or directly".[47]

At the end of the 1990s, Habermas approached Derrida at a party held at an American university where both were lecturing. They then met at Paris over dinner, and participated afterwards in many joint projects. In 2000 they held a joint seminar on problems of philosophy, right, ethics, and politics at the University of Frankfurt.[47] In December 2000, in Paris, Habermas gave a lecture entitled "How to answer the ethical question?" at the Judeities. Questions for Jacques Derrida conference organized by Joseph Cohen and Raphael Zagury-Orly. Following the lecture by Habermas, both thinkers engaged in a very heated debate on Heidegger and the possibility of Ethics. The conference volume was published at the Editions Galilée (Paris) in 2002, and subsequently in English at Fordham University Press (2007).

In the aftermath of the 11 September attacks, Derrida and Habermas laid out their individual opinions on 9/11 and the War on Terror in Giovanna Borradori's Philosophy in a Time of Terror: Dialogues with Jürgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida. In early 2003, both Habermas and Derrida were very active in opposing the coming Iraq War; in a manifesto that later became the book Old Europe, New Europe, Core Europe, the two called for a tighter unification of the states of the European Union in order to create a power capable of opposing American foreign policy. Derrida wrote a foreword expressing his unqualified subscription to Habermas's declaration of February 2003 ("February 15, or, What Binds Europeans Together: Plea for a Common Foreign Policy, Beginning in Core Europe") in the book, which was a reaction to the Bush administration's demands upon European nations for support in the coming Iraq War.[50] Habermas has offered further context for this declaration in an interview.[citation needed]

Religious dialogue

Habermas's attitudes toward religion have changed throughout the years. Analyst Phillippe Portier identifies three phases in Habermas's attitude towards this social sphere: the first, in the decade of 1980, when the younger Jürgen, in the spirit of Marx, argued against religion seeing it as an "alienating reality" and "control tool"; the second phase, from the mid-1980s to the beginning of the 21st century, when he stopped discussing it and, as a secular commentator, relegated it to matters of private life; and the third, from then until now, when Habermas saw a positive social role of religion.[51]

In an interview in 1999 Habermas had stated:

For the normative self-understanding of modernity, Christianity has functioned as more than just a precursor or catalyst. Universalistic egalitarianism, from which sprang the ideals of freedom and a collective life in solidarity, the autonomous conduct of life and emancipation, the individual morality of conscience, human rights and democracy, is the direct legacy of the Judaic ethic of justice and the Christian ethic of love. This legacy, substantially unchanged, has been the object of a continual critical reappropriation and reinterpretation. Up to this very day there is no alternative to it. And in light of the current challenges of a post-national constellation, we must draw sustenance now, as in the past, from this substance. Everything else is idle postmodern talk.[52][53][54]

The original German (from the Habermas Forum website) of the disputed quotation is:

Das Christentum ist für das normative Selbstverständnis der Moderne nicht nur eine Vorläufergestalt oder ein Katalysator gewesen. Der egalitäre Universalismus, aus dem die Ideen von Freiheit und solidarischem Zusammenleben, von autonomer Lebensführung und Emanzipation, von individueller Gewissensmoral, Menschenrechten und Demokratie entsprungen sind, ist unmittelbar ein Erbe der jüdischen Gerechtigkeits- und der christlichen Liebesethik. In der Substanz unverändert, ist dieses Erbe immer wieder kritisch angeeignet und neu interpretiert worden. Dazu gibt es bis heute keine Alternative. Auch angesichts der aktuellen Herausforderungen einer postnationalen Konstellation zehren wir nach wie vor von dieser Substanz. Alles andere ist postmodernes Gerede.

— Jürgen Habermas, Zeit der Übergänge (2001), p. 174f.

This statement has been misquoted in a number of articles and books, where Habermas instead is quoted for saying:

Christianity, and nothing else, is the ultimate foundation of liberty, conscience, human rights, and democracy, the benchmarks of Western civilization. To this day, we have no other options. We continue to nourish ourselves from this source. Everything else is postmodern chatter.[55][56]

In his book Zwischen Naturalismus und Religion (Between Naturalism and Religion, 2005), Habermas stated that the forces of religious strength, as a result of multiculturalism and immigration, are stronger than in previous decades, and, therefore, there is a need of tolerance which must be understood as a two-way street: secular people need to tolerate the role of religious people in the public square and vice versa.[57][58]

In early 2007, Ignatius Press published a dialogue between Habermas and the then Prefect of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith of the Holy Office Joseph Ratzinger (elected as Pope Benedict XVI in 2005), entitled The Dialectics of Secularization. The dialogue took place on 14 January 2004 after an invitation to both thinkers by the Catholic Academy of Bavaria in Munich.[59] It addressed contemporary questions such as:

In this debate a shift of Habermas became evident—in particular, his rethinking of the public role of religion. Habermas stated that he wrote as a "methodological atheist," which means that when doing philosophy or social science, he presumed nothing about particular religious beliefs. Yet while writing from this perspective his evolving position towards the role of religion in society led him to some challenging questions, and as a result conceding some ground in his dialogue with the future Pope, that would seem to have consequences which further complicated the positions he holds about a communicative rational solution to the problems of modernity. Habermas believes that even for self-identified liberal thinkers, "to exclude religious voices from the public square is highly illiberal."

In addition, Habermas has popularized the concept of "post-secular" society, to refer to current times in which the idea of modernity is perceived as unsuccessful and at times, morally failed, so that, rather than a stratification or separation, a new peaceful dialogue and coexistence between faith and reason must be sought in order to learn mutually.[60]

Socialist dialogue

Habermas has sided with other 20th-century commentators on Marx such as Hannah Arendt who have indicated concerns with the limits of totalitarian perspectives often associated with Marx's over-estimation of the emancipatory potential of the forces of production. Arendt had presented this in her book The Origins of Totalitarianism and Habermas extends this critique in his writings on functional reductionism in the life-world in his Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason. As Habermas states:

…traditional Marxist analysis… today, when we use the means of the critique of political economy… can no longer make clear predictions: for that, one would still have to assume the autonomy of a self-reproducing economic system. I do not believe in such an autonomy. Precisely for this reason, the laws governing the economic system are no longer identical to the ones Marx analyzed. Of course, this does not mean that it would be wrong to analyze the mechanism which drives the economic system; but in order for the orthodox version of such an analysis to be valid, the influence of the political system would have to be ignored.[17]

Habermas reiterated the positions that what refuted Marx and his theory of class struggle was the "pacification of class conflict" by the welfare state, which had developed in the West "since 1945", thanks to "a reformist relying on the instruments of Keynesian economics".[61][62] Italian philosopher and historian Domenico Losurdo criticised the main point of these claims as "marked by the absence of a question that should be obvious:— Was the advent of the welfare state the inevitable result of a tendency inherent in capitalism? Or was it the result of political and social mobilization by the subaltern classes—in the final analysis, of a class struggle? Had the German philosopher posed this question, perhaps he would have avoided assuming the permanence of the welfare state, whose precariousness and progressive dismantlement are now obvious to everyone".[62]

Controversy about wars

In 1999, Habermas addressed the Kosovo War. Habermas defended NATO's intervention in an article for Die Zeit, which stirred controversy.[63]

In 2001, Habermas argued that the United States should not go to war in Iraq.[64]

European Union

During the European debt crisis, Habermas criticized Angela Merkel's leadership in Europe. In 2013, Habermas clashed with Wolfgang Streeck, who argued the kind of European federalism espoused by Habermas as the root of the continent's crisis.[65]

Awards

Major works

  • The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere (1962) ISBN 0-262-58108-6
  • Theory and Practice (1963)
  • On the Logic of the Social Sciences (1967)
  • Toward a Rational Society (1968)
  • Technology and Science as Ideology (1968)
  • Knowledge and Human Interests (1971, German 1968)
  • Legitimation Crisis (1975)
  • Communication and the Evolution of Society (1976)
  • On the Pragmatics of Social Interaction (1976)
  • The Theory of Communicative Action (1981)
  • Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (1983)
  • Philosophical-Political Profiles (1983)
  • The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity (1985)
  • The New Conservatism (1985)
  • The New Obscurity: The Crisis of the Welfare State (1986)
  • Postmetaphysical Thinking (1988)
  • Justification and Application (1991)
  • Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy (1992)
  • On the Pragmatics of Communication (1992)
  • The Inclusion of the Other (1996)
  • A Berlin Republic (1997, collection of interviews with Habermas)
  • The Postnational Constellation (1998)
  • Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God, and Modernity (1998)
  • Truth and Justification (1998)
  • The Future of Human Nature (2003) ISBN 0-7456-2986-5
  • Old Europe, New Europe, Core Europe (2005) ISBN 1-84467-018-X
  • The Divided West (2006)
  • The Dialectics of Secularization (2007, w/ Joseph Ratzinger)
  • Between Naturalism and Religion: Philosophical Essays (2008)
  • Europe. The Faltering Project (2009)
  • The Crisis of the European Union (2012)
  • This Too a History of Philosophy (2019)
  • A New Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere and Deliberative Politics (2023)

See also

References

  1. ^ "Pragmatism". iep.utm.edu. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  2. ^ Bordum, Anders (2005). "Immanuel Kant, Jürgen Habermas and the categorical imperative". Philosophy & Social Criticism. 31 (7).
  3. ^ "Habermas". Collins English Dictionary.
  4. ^ Max Mangold and Dudenredaktion: Duden Aussprachewörterbuch. In: Der Duden in zwölf Bänden. Volume 6, 6th edition, Dudenverlag, Mannheim/Leipzig/Wien/Zürich 2005 ISBN 978-3-411-04066-7, "Jürgen" p. 446 and "Habermas" p. 383.
  5. ^ Krech, Eva-Maria; Stock, Eberhard; Hirschfeld, Ursula; Anders, Lutz Christian (2009). Deutsches Aussprachewörterbuch [German Pronunciation Dictionary] (in German). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 561, 629. ISBN 978-3-11-018202-6.
  6. ^ Cf. Thomas Kupka, Jürgen Habermas' diskurstheoretische Reformulierung des klassischen Vernunftrechts, Kritische Justiz 27 (1994), pp. 461–469. The continuity with the natural law tradition was controversial at the time, see the reply by Habermas's PhD-student Klaus Günther, Diskurstheorie des Rechts oder liberales Naturrecht in diskurstheoretischem Gewande?, Kritische Justiz 27 (1994), pp. 470–487.
  7. ^ "The philosopher who rejected a €225,000 prize from the UAE – DW – 05/03/2021". dw.com. Retrieved 28 March 2024.
  8. ^ Simplican, Clifford; Stacy (28 October 2017). "Disabling Democracy: How Disability Reconfigures Deliberative Democratic Norms". SSRN 1451092.
  9. ^ Habermas, Jürgen (2008). "First". Between Naturalism and Religion: Philosophical Essays.
  10. ^ a b Habermas, Jürgen (1954). "Das Absolute und die Geschichte" [The Absolute and History]. University Library Heidelberg (in German). doi:10.11588/DIGLIT.41402. Retrieved 3 December 2022.
  11. ^ Calhoun, Craig J. (2002). Contemporary Sociological Theory. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 352. ISBN 0-631-21350-3.
  12. ^ f "Book of Members, 1780–2010: Chapter H". American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Retrieved 19 April 2011. {{cite web}}: Check |url= value (help)
  13. ^ Jürgen Habermas (2004) Public space and political public sphere – the biographical roots of two motifs in my thought.(Commemorative Lecture, Kyoto) Archived 4 February 2012 at the Wayback Machine (pp. 2–4)
  14. ^ "The most cited authors of books in the humanities". timeshighereducation.co.uk. 26 March 2009. Retrieved 16 November 2009.
  15. ^ Buhmann, Alexander; Ihlen, Øyvind; Aaen-Stockdale, Craig (4 November 2019). "Connecting the dots: a bibliometric review of Habermasian theory in public relations research". Journal of Communication Management. 23 (4): 444–467. doi:10.1108/JCOM-12-2018-0127. hdl:10852/74987. ISSN 1363-254X. S2CID 210568613.
  16. ^ Lew Rockwell, introduction to Hoppe's A Short History of Man (2015), Auburn, Mississippi: Mises Institute, p. 9.
  17. ^ a b c Habermas, Jürgen (1981). Kleine Politische Schrifen I-IV (in German). p. 500.
  18. ^ Müller-Doohm, Stefan (2008). Jürgen Habermas. Suhrkamp BasisBiographie. Vol. 38. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
  19. ^ a b Calhoun 2002, p. 351
  20. ^ Corchia, Luca (1 September 2008). "Explicative models of complexity. The reconstructions of social evolution for Jürgen Habermas". In Balbi, S; Scepi, G; Russolillo, G; et al. (eds.). Book of Short Abstracts. Vol. 7th International Conference on Social Science Methodology – RC33 – Logic and Methodology in Sociology. Napoli, IT: Jovene Editore.
  21. ^ a b Blanning, T. C. W. (1998) [1987]. The French Revolution Class War or Culture Clash? (2nd ed.). New York: St. Martin's Press. p. 26.
  22. ^ a b Blanning 1998, pp. 26–27
  23. ^ a b c d e f Blanning 1998, p. 27
  24. ^ a b c d e Calhoun 2002, p. 353
  25. ^ a b Calhoun 2002, p. 354
  26. ^ Payrow Shabani, Omid A. (2003). Democracy, Power and Legitimacy: The Critical Theory of Jürgen Habermas. University of Toronto Press. p. 49. ISBN 978-0-8020-8761-4.
  27. ^ a b Calhoun 2002, p. 355
  28. ^ Habermas, Jürgen; Ben-Habib, Seyla (1981). "Modernity versus Postmodernity". New German Critique (22): 3–14. doi:10.2307/487859. ISSN 0094-033X. JSTOR 487859.
  29. ^ a b Ritzer, George (2008). "Sociological Theory". From Modern to Postmodern Social Theory (and Beyond). New York, New York: McGraw-Hill. pp. 567–568.
  30. ^ Barthold, Lauren Swayne. "Hans-Georg Gadamer (1900—2002)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 22 February 2023.
  31. ^ Gamwell, Franklin I. (1997). "Habermas and Apel on communicative ethics: Their difference and the difference it makes". Philosophy and Social Criticism. 23 (2): 21–45. doi:10.1177/019145379702300202. S2CID 144776550.
  32. ^ Habermas, Jürgen (1995). "Reconciliation Through the Public Use of Reason: Remarks on John Rawls's Political Liberalism". Journal of Philosophy. 92 (3): 109–131.
  33. ^ Rawls, John (1995). "Political Liberalism: Reply to Habermas". Journal of Philosophy. 92 (3): 132–180.
  34. ^ a b Habermas, Jürgen (1993). "A Kind of Settlement of Damages On Apologetic Tendencies In German History Writing". In Piper, Ernst (ed.). Forever In the Shadow of Hitler?. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press. pp. 34–44 [43].
  35. ^ Habermas, Jürgen (1993). "A Kind of Settlement of Damages On Apologetic Tendencies In German History Writing". In Piper, Ernst (ed.). Forever In the Shadow of Hitler?. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press. pp. 34–44 [42–43].
  36. ^ Habermas, Jürgen (1993). "A Kind of Settlement of Damages On Apologetic Tendencies In German History Writing". In Piper, Ernst (ed.). Forever In the Shadow of Hitler?. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press. pp. 34–44 [37–38].
  37. ^ Fest, Joachim (1993). "Encumbered Remembrance: The Controversy about the Incomparability of National-Socialist Mass Crimes". In Piper, Ernst (ed.). Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press. pp. 63–71 [64–65].
  38. ^ Fest, Joachim (1993). "Postscript, April 21, 1987". In Piper, Ernst (ed.). Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press. pp. 264–265.
  39. ^ Schulze, Hagen (1993). "Questions We Have To Face: No Historical Stance without National Identity". In Piper, Ernst (ed.). Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press. pp. 93–97 [94].
  40. ^ Möller, Horst (1993). "What May Not Be, Cannot Be: A Plea for Rendering Factual the Controversy about Recent History". In Piper, Ernst (ed.). Forever In The Shadow of Hitler?. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press. pp. 216–221 [216–218].
  41. ^ Geiss, Imanuel (1993). "On the Historikerstreit". In Piper, Ernst (ed.). Forever In The Shadow Of Hitler?. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press. pp. 254–258 [256].
  42. ^ Hildebrand, Klaus, "The Age of Tyrants: History and Politics The Administrators of the Enlightenment, the Risk of Scholarship and the Preservation of a Worldview A Reply to Jürgen Habermas", pp. 50–55, & "He Who Wants To Escape the Abyss Will Have Sound It Very Precisely: Is the New German History Writing Revisionist?" pp. 188–195 from Forever In The Shadow of Hitler? ed. Piper (1993).
  43. ^ Broszat, Martin, "Where the Roads Part: History Is Not A Suitable Substitute for a Religion of Nationalism", pp. 123–129, Forever In The Shadow of Hitler? ed. Piper (1993), p. 127.
  44. ^ Jäckel, Eberhard, "The Impoverished Practice of Insinuation: The Singular Aspect of National Socialist Crimes Cannot Be Denied", pp. 74–78 from Forever In The Shadow of Hitler? ed. Piper (1993), pp. 74–75.
  45. ^ Mommsen, Hans, "The New Historical Consciousness and the Relativizing of National Socialism", pp. 114–124 from Forever In The Shadow of Hitler? ed. Piper (1993), pp. 114–115.
  46. ^ Evans, Richard, In Hitler's Shadow, New York: Pantheon Books, 1989, pp. 159–160.
  47. ^ a b c Derrida, J (2006), Lasse Thomassen (ed.), "Honesty of Thought", The Derrida-Habermas Reader, Chicago Ill: The University of Chicago Press, p. 302, ISBN 978-0-226-79683-3
  48. ^ Thomassen, L. "Introduction: Between Deconstruction and Rational Reconstruction" in The Derrida-Habermas Reader, ed. Thomassen (2006), pp. 1–7. P.2.
  49. ^ Derrida, J., "Is There a Philosophical Language?" in The Derrida-Habermas Reader, ed. Thomassen (2006), pp. 35–45. P.37.
  50. ^ Habermas, J. and Derrida, J. "February 15, Or What Binds Europeans Together: A Plea for a Common Foreign Policy, beginning in the Core of Europe" in The Derrida-Habermas Reader, ed. Thomassen (2006), pp. 270–277. P. 302.
  51. ^ Sánchez, Rosalía. 2011. 'San' Jürgen Habermas. El Mundo. Access date: 10 January 2015
  52. ^ Habermas, Jurgen, Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God, and Modernity, ed. Eduardo Mendieta, MIT Press, 2002, p. 149. And Habermas, Jurgen, Time of Transitions, Polity Press, 2006, pp. 150–151.
  53. ^ First Principles Journal– Recovering the Western Soul, Wilfred M. McClay (from IR 42:1, Spring 2007) – 01/01/09. Accessed: 2 December 2012.
  54. ^ Secularization and Cultural Criticism: Religion, Nation, and Modernity, Vincent P. Pecora..
  55. ^ "A misquote about Habermas and Christianity". habermas-rawls.blogspot.fi. 8 June 2009. Retrieved 28 October 2017.
  56. ^ Ambrose Ih-Ren Mong. Dialogue Derailed: Joseph Ratzinger's War against Pluralist Theology. Wipf and Stock Publishers. p. 279
  57. ^ A "post-secular" society – what does that mean? Archived 29 March 2009 at the Wayback Machine by Jurgen Habermas, June 2008.
  58. ^ Espinosa, Javier. "The religion in the public sphere. Habermas, Toland and Spinoza" (PDF). Universidad de Castilla-La Mancha. Archived from the original (PDF) on 8 January 2016.
  59. ^ (Papst), Benedikt XVI; Habermas, Jürgen (28 October 2017). Dialectics of Secularization: On Reason and Religion. Ignatius Press. ISBN 978-1-58617-166-7. Retrieved 28 October 2017 – via Google Books.
  60. ^ Buston, Fernando del. 2014. El Estado debe proteger a la religión. El Comercio. Date access 10 January 2015: "Jürgen Habermas ha acuñado el término de postsecularidad.Se da por fallida la idea central de la modernidad de que la religión iba a desaparecer y se establece una nueva relación entre razón y religión. Habermas plantea que es necesario emprender un aprendizaje mutuo entre las sociedades modernas y las creencias, o entre razón secular y fe. Se inicia una nueva época de mutuas tolerancias. La razón no puede echar por la borda el potencial de sentido de las religiones y éstas deben traducir sus contenidos racionalmente."
  61. ^ Habermas, Jürgen (1987). Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 2. Translated by Thomas, McCarthy. Beacon Press. p. 348.
  62. ^ a b Losurdo, Domenico (2016). Class Struggle. Palgrave Macmillan. p. 3. doi:10.1057/978-1-349-70660-0. ISBN 978-1-137-52387-7. LCCN 2016940579. S2CID 265035687.
  63. ^ Jürgen Habermas, 'Bestialität und Humanität: Ein Krieg an der Grenze zwischen Recht und Moral', Die Zeit, 29 April 1999; in English as 'Bestiality and Humanity: A War on the Border between Law and Morality', in William Buckley (ed.), Kosovo: Contending Voices on the Balkan Intervention (2000).
  64. ^ Jürgen Habermas, "Letter to America", The Nation, 16 December 2002
  65. ^ Philip Oltermann, "Merkel 'gambling away' Germany's reputation over Greece, says Habermas", The Guardian (16 July 2015)
  66. ^ "VIKTOR FRANKL AWARD". 19 June 2017. Archived from the original on 19 June 2017.
  67. ^ "Georg-August-Zinn-Preis – SPD Hessen im Internet". Archived from the original on 24 October 2012. Retrieved 17 September 2012.
  68. ^ "The future of democracy, with Jürgen Habermas". KNAW. Retrieved 6 November 2013.
  69. ^ "German philosopher Habermas rejects UAE's Zayed Book Award". AP NEWS. 2 May 2021. Retrieved 2 May 2021.
  70. ^ SPIEGEL, Dietmar Pieper, DER (2 May 2021). "Jürgen Habermas und die emiratische Propaganda: Lässt sich der Starphilosoph vereinnahmen?". Der Spiegel (in German). Retrieved 2 May 2021.{{cite news}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  71. ^ "Jürgen Habermas turns down UAE award over human rights concerns". DW. 2 May 2021.
  72. ^ "Jürgen Habermas Awarded Inaugural Dialectic Medal" https://www.dialecticinstitute.org/medal/habermas.htm
  73. ^ "Habermas". ORDEN POUR LE MÉRITE (in German). Retrieved 11 June 2023.

Further reading

  • Gregg Daniel Miller, Mimesis and Reason: Habermas's Political Philosophy. SUNY Press, 2011.
A recent analysis which underscores the aesthetic power of intersubjective communication in Habermas's theory of communicative action.
  • Jürgen Habermas: a philosophical—political profile by Marvin Rintala, Perspectives on Political Science, 2002-01-01
  • Jürgen Habermas by Martin Matuštík (2001) ISBN 0-7425-0796-3
  • Postnational identity: critical theory and existential philosophy in Habermas, Kierkegaard, and Havel by Martin Matuštík (1993) ISBN 0-89862-420-7
  • Thomas McCarthy, The Critical Theory of Jürgen Habermas, MIT Press, 1978.
A highly regarded interpretation in English of Habermas's earlier work, written just as Habermas was developing his full-fledged communication theory.
  • Raymond Geuss, The Idea of a Critical Theory, Cambridge University Press, 1981.
A clear account of Habermas's early philosophical views.
  • J.G. Finlayson, Habermas: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford University Press, 2004.
A recent, brief introduction to Habermas, focusing on his communication theory of society.
Discussing Habermas's legal philosophy in the 1992 original German edition of Between Facts and Norms.
  • Andreas Dorschel: 'Handlungstypen und Kriterien. Zu Habermas' Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, in: Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 44 (1990), nr. 2, pp. 220–252. A critical discussion of types of action in Habermas. In German.
  • Erik Oddvar Eriksen and Jarle Weigard, Understanding Habermas: Communicative Action and Deliberative Democracy, Continuum International Publishing, 2004 (ISBN 0-8264-7179-X).
A recent and comprehensive introduction to Habermas's mature theory and its political implications both national and global.
  • Alexandre Guilherme and W.John Morgan,'Habermas(1929–)-dialogue as communicative rationality', Chapter 9 in Philosophy, Dialogue, and Education: Nine modern European philosophers, Routledge, London and New York, pp. 140– 154. ISBN 978-1-138-83149-0.
  • Detlef Horster. Habermas: An Introduction. Pennbridge, 1992 (ISBN 1-880055-01-5)
  • Martin Jay, Marxism and Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from Lukacs to Habermas (Chapter 9), University of California Press, 1986. (ISBN 0-520-05742-2)
  • Ernst Piper (ed.) "Historikerstreit": Die Dokumentation der Kontroverse um die Einzigartigkeit der nationalsozialistschen Judenvernichtung, Munich: Piper, 1987, translated into English by James Knowlton and Truett Cates as Forever In The Shadow Of Hitler?: Original Documents Of the Historikerstreit, The Controversy Concerning The Singularity Of The Holocaust, Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1993 (ISBN 0-391-03784-6) Contains Habermas's essays from the Historikerstreit and the reactions of various scholars to his statements.
  • Edgar, Andrew. The Philosophy of Habermas. Мontreal, McGill-Queen's UP, 2005.
  • Adams, Nicholas. Habermas & Theology. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2006.
  • Mike Sandbothe, Habermas, Pragmatism, and the Media, Online publication: sandbothe.net 2008; German original in: Über Habermas. Gespräche mit Zeitgenossen, ed. by Michael Funken, Darmstadt: Primus, 2008.
  • Müller-Doohm, Stefan. Jürgen Habermas. Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, 2008 (Suhrkamp BasisBiographie, 38).
  • Moderne Religion? Theologische und religionsphilosophische Reaktionen auf Jürgen Habermas. Hrsg. v. Knut Wenzel und Thomas M. Schmidt. Freiburg, Herder, 2009.
  • Luca Corchia, Jürgen Habermas. A bibliography: works and studies (1952–2013): With an Introduction by Stefan Müller-Doohm, Arnus Edizioni – Il Campano, Pisa, 2013.
  • Corchia, Luca (April 2018). Jürgen Habermas. A Bibliography. 1. Works of Jürgen Habermas (1952–2018). Department of Political Science, University of Pisa (Italy), 156 pp..
  • Corchia, Luca (February 2016). Jürgen Habermas. A bibliography. 2. Studies on Jürgen Habermas (1962–2015). Department of Political Science, University of Pisa (Italy), 468 pp..
  • Peter Koller, Christian Hiebaum, Jürgen Habermas: Faktizität und Geltung, Walter de Gruyter, 2016.

External links

Awards
Preceded by Theodor W. Adorno Award
1980
Succeeded by
Preceded by Sonning Prize
1987
Succeeded by
Preceded by Princess of Asturias Award
for Social Sciences

2003
Succeeded by
Preceded by Kyoto Prize in Arts and Philosophy
2004
Succeeded by
Preceded by Holberg Prize
2005
Succeeded by
Preceded by Erasmus Prize
2013
Succeeded by
Preceded by Kluge Prize
2015
With: Charles Taylor
Succeeded by